school children’s ability to distinguish hypothetical beliefs

Upload: 119568

Post on 03-Jun-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    1/9

    Elementary School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical BeliefsFrom Statements of Preference

    Irene-Anna N. DiakidoyUniversity of Cyprus

    Christos IoannidesUniversity of Pireaus

    The authors examined students understanding of hypotheses as beliefs that can be empirically verified.

    Thirty second graders and 30 sixth graders considered cases of disagreement about foods and colors that

    reflected either alternative hypotheses or different preferences. Their task was to decide whether the

    validity of each expressed belief could be determined and to justify their decision. Younger students

    considered both hypotheses and preferences as empirically verifiable, whereas older students were better

    able to recognize in some cases that preferences are legitimately variable. This lack of distinction may

    reflect limited metaconceptual ability or a deterministic epistemological view, both of which might

    interfere with the understanding of the hypothesis-testing process.

    In the past 15 years, there has been a proliferation of research

    exploring issues related to the acquisition of scientific knowledge

    and skills (Ioannides & Vosniadou, 2002; Klaczynski, 2000;

    Klahr, Fay, & Dunbar, 1993; Kuhn, Amsel, & OLoughlin, 1988;

    Sodian, Zaitchik, & Carey, 1991) as well as to the teaching of

    science in elementary and secondary schools (Guzzetti, Snyder,

    Glass, & Gamas, 1993; Smith, Maclin, Grosslight, & Davis, 1997;

    Toth, Klahr, & Chen, 2000). One line of this research has explic-

    itly focused on the knowledge and skills that are taken to underlie

    the understanding and the application of the scientific method (see,

    e.g., Kuhn, Black, Keselman, & Kaplan, 2000). A central part of

    this knowledge is the understanding of the hypothesis as a causal

    or categorical statement that accounts for a particular state ofaffairs. The scientific method revolves around the formulation and

    empirical testing of hypotheses, and conclusions regarding their

    validity enrich, modify, or restructure scientific knowledge. The

    present study focused on the understanding of hypotheses as

    statements or assertions whose truth value can be determined, at

    least to some extent, through empirical testing.

    Studies by Kuhn and her colleagues (e.g., Kuhn et al., 1988;

    Kuhn, Garcia-Mila, Zohar, & Andersen, 1995) have documented

    preadolescent childrens weaknesses in scientific reasoning and,

    specifically, in the ability to test causal hypotheses in a systematic

    way. Kuhn has interpreted these findings as attributable to a lack

    of differentiation between prior belief and the evidence that may

    confirm or disconfirm it (Kuhn et al., 1988). On the other hand,

    Sodian et al. (1991) have shown that first and second graders can

    distinguish between conclusive and inconclusive tests of simple

    hypotheses when these are presented to them. This finding led

    Sodian et al. to the contrasting conclusion than even young chil-

    dren can differentiate between a belief and the evidence that may

    support or disconfirm it. The ability to differentiate between belief

    and evidence is crucial to understanding the function and potential

    outcomes of hypothesis testing in science domains. Equally cru-

    cial, however, is the ability to understand what types of beliefs

    would constitute a hypothesis and would, therefore, be subject to

    empirical verification.

    Hypotheses as a Subset of Belief Statements

    To the extent that a hypothesis is promoted by one or more

    individuals as a (potentially) true or valid account of a state of

    affairs, it can be taken to represent a belief that, nevertheless, is

    subject to disconfirmation on the basis of evidence. The opposite,

    however, is not necessarily true. Only a subset of statements or

    assertions from the universe of beliefs can be subject to discon-

    firmation and therefore constitute legitimate hypotheses of the type

    that would lend themselves to systematic scientific inquiry

    (Dewey, 1906; Stace, 1945). This point is more clearly illustrated

    by considering one such subset of beliefs that could be taken, more

    appropriately, to represent preferences. The assertion Red is a

    more beautiful color than blue represents an evaluative proposi-

    tion (Dworkin, 1996) that can be classified as a personal prefer-

    ence. It also represents a belief to the extent that it is held to be true

    by at least one person (Southerland, Sinatra, & Matthews, 2001).

    As it is formulated, however, its generalizability is indeterminate,

    and therefore, it cannot be subjected to the empirical test. On the

    other hand, the validity and generalizability of the related assertion

    Most people think that red is a more beautiful color than blue

    can be determined, and therefore, it can function as a legitimate

    hypothesis. The outstanding difference between these statements

    of beliefthe hypothesis and the preferenceis that one can be

    subjected to the empirical test whereas the other cannot because it

    Irene-Anna N. Diakidoy, Department of Education, University of

    Cyprus, Nicosia, Cyprus; Christos Ioannides, Department of Education,

    University of Piraeus, Piraeus, Greece.

    The authors made equal contributions to this article so author names

    appear in alphabetical order.

    We thank D. Natsopoulos for reviewing an earlier draft of the manu-

    script, A. Raftopoulos for his comments about the philosophical distinc-

    tions between kinds of beliefs, A. Andreou for his help with data collection,

    and the children who participated in the study.

    Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Irene-

    Anna N. Diakidoy, Department of Education, University of Cyprus, Kal-

    lipoleos 75, P.O. Box 20537, CY-1678 Nicosia, Cyprus. E-mail:

    [email protected]

    Journal of Educational Psychology Copyright 2004 by the American Psychological Association2004, Vol. 96, No. 3, 536 544 0022-0663/04/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/0022-0663.96.3.536

    536

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    2/9

    concerns a matter of personal taste (Carpendale & Chandler,

    1996).

    The understanding of this difference can be taken to reflect the

    development of metacognitive competence (Kuhn et al., 1995) to

    the extent that it implicates a reflection on the types of beliefs that

    one may hold. As such, it presupposes the understanding of belief

    as a mental state distinct from physical fact (Perner, 1991) but fallsshort of the sophisticated metastrategic competence that is in-

    volved in the coordination of multiple sources of evidence with

    theory and that preadolescents have been found to lack (Kuhn et

    al., 1988). It is, however, intimately connected with the ability to

    recognize and/or formulate researchable questions and therefore is

    a prerequisite to understanding the function of the scientific

    method and its successful application. The immersion of students

    in the scientific process, as in the case of inquiry-based learning,

    involves, among other things, their active participation in the

    formulation and testing of hypotheses (Chinn & Malhotra, 2002;

    McGinn & Roth, 1999). It would appear, then, that the understand-

    ing of hypotheses as a distinct set of beliefs defined by their

    potential to be empirically verified would justify, to the mind of

    the student, the process of testing them in the context of scientific

    inquiry. That same understanding can be expected to highlight the

    tentative and evolving nature of scientific knowledge (Elby &

    Hammer, 2001; Polanyi, 1950), promoting thereby the develop-

    ment of more sophisticated epistemological views (Carey & Smith,

    1993; Southerland et al., 2001).

    The ability to differentiate hypotheses from other belief state-

    ments, such as preferences, is also related to the ability to differ-

    entiate hypotheses from evidence (Sodian et al., 1991) but only to

    the extent that it involves theat least implicitrecognition that

    the truth value of a belief is supportable by facts or reasons that are

    distinct from the belief itself. The child, for example, who offers an

    explicit reason for holding a belief of any kind that is not a simple

    restatement of the belief itself demonstrates a basic understandingthat reasons represent distinct entities that are brought to bear on

    beliefs. This understanding, however, does not necessarily imply

    the ability to distinguish between different types of belief that, to

    our mind, would also have implications concerning the ability to

    distinguish between the various types of information or reasons

    that can support them. Therefore, the highly constrained context of

    the Sodian et al. (1991) study (i.e., children had to choose between

    two tests that could yield either conclusive or inconclusive, but

    otherwise appropriate, evidence concerning the validity of two

    simple and mutually exclusive hypotheses) does not permit any

    inferences concerning the extent to which children recognized the

    presented contrasting beliefs as hypotheses.

    Distinguishing Hypotheses From Other Belief Statements

    Despite its importance with respect to the acquisition of scien-

    tific knowledge and skills, the ability to distinguish between hy-

    potheses and other types of beliefs has not been the subject of

    intense investigation within the areas of cognitive-developmental

    and educational psychology. However, one study by Carpendale

    and Chandler (1996) has implications with respect to this issue.

    Their study was designed to assess childrens ability to understand

    and account for differences in interpretation and preference in

    relation to their understanding of false belief. In addition to a

    standard false belief task, they also presented 5- to 6-year-old and

    7- to 8-year-old children with scenarios in which two puppets

    disagreed on matters of taste (e.g., which soup was tastier and

    which picture was nicer) or arrived at a different interpretation of

    an ambiguous stimulus. The ambiguous stimulus tasks involved

    lexical ambiguity (e.g., having to wait for a ring), referential

    ambiguity (e.g., object hidden under two equally large blocks),

    and figural ambiguity (e.g., duckrabbit and ratman drawings).

    For each scenario, children were asked to indicate whether it wasall right for the puppets to disagree and to justify their answer.

    Indications that the different interpretations or tastes were equally

    acceptable were scored as correct responses. Carpendale and

    Chandlers results showed that childrens scores on the matter-of-

    taste tasks were significantly different from their scores on the

    ambiguous stimuli tasks. Overall, all children were more likely to

    indicate that differences in preference were more acceptable than

    differences in interpretation. More importantly, however, there

    was also a significant main effect of age, indicating that the older

    children were more likely to correctly attribute differences in

    preference to matters of personal taste and differences in interpre-

    tation to the ambiguous nature of the stimuli.

    Acknowledging variations in preference as more acceptable

    than variations in interpretation reflects a basic recognition of

    these statements of belief as different in some respects. In the

    Carpendale and Chandler (1996) study, however, the conflicting

    preferences and interpretations were equally acceptable. What

    distinguished them was the source of their justification (i.e., person

    based as opposed to stimulus based) and their potential to be

    verified as true and generalizable. What Carpendale and Chandler

    termed interpretations could essentially be conceptualized as cat-

    egorical hypotheses concerning the nature or the meaning of an

    ambiguous stimulus. Therefore, one could verify them the same

    way one would test such a hypothesis: by collecting more infor-

    mation about the stimulus in question and its relation to other

    stimuli. In contrast, one would not be able to arrive at a similar

    generalizable conclusion concerning variations in preference.Their validity must be taken at face value because the observed

    variations derive from personal subjective experience and neither

    need nor admit external justification.

    The fact that the older children were better able to distinguish

    preferences from interpretations on the basis of differences in

    sources of origin and justification (Carpendale & Chandler, 1996)

    reflects the development of an understanding of a fundamental

    way in which various beliefs may differ from each other. However,

    it does not necessarily reflect a corresponding understanding that

    what further distinguishes a particular set of beliefs is their poten-

    tial for empirical validation. Therefore, the present study sought to

    assess the extent to which elementary school children could dif-

    ferentiate hypotheses from other beliefs as statements whose truth

    value can be decided upon on the basis of empirical testing. The

    sample included second graders, whose age range corresponded to

    that of the older children in the Carpendale and Chandler (1996)

    study, and sixth graders. The choice of the sample was motivated,

    first, by the fact that it is in elementary school that children come

    formally into contact with scientific knowledge and activities as

    such and, second, by the possibility of a developmental progres-

    sion toward a more mature understanding of what would constitute

    a hypothesis and an empirical test in relation to that formal

    exposure. We expected, then, that the sixth-grade students would

    be better able to recognize that the validity of a hypothesis can be

    determined whereas the validity of a preference must be taken at

    face value.

    537DIFFERENTIATING HYPOTHESES FROM PREFERENCES

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    3/9

    Our basic procedure was similar to the one used by Carpendale

    and Chandler (1996) in the sense that we also presented partici-

    pants with scenarios of disagreement about foods and colors that

    reflected either a difference in preference or alternative hypotheses

    of the type that could be the focus of scientific investigation.

    However, instead of asking children to decide whether the dis-

    agreement was acceptable, we asked them to decide whether onecould determine which side was right or wrong and to justify their

    decision. We asked for a justification because a positive answer

    with respect to whether the validity of a particular assertion could

    be determined would not permit any inferences regarding chil-

    drens understanding of what would constitute a hypothesis test.

    For example, a child, or an adult for that matter, might indicate that

    the validity of an assertion can be determined by asking an expert

    or by reading. Although this would certainly influence ones

    gravitation toward one side of an issue, it would not count as

    legitimate empirical evidence on the basis of which hypotheses are

    evaluated in science domains. Moreover, one could indicate that a

    decision can be based on appearance and taste comparisons. In this

    case, a belief is justified on the basis of subjective evaluation, and

    although this is a way of assessing whether one shares a prefer-

    ence, it would not count as a legitimate hypothesis test.

    Research has shown that prior knowledge and personal beliefs

    can influence reasoning (see, e.g., Stanovich & West, 1997), the

    extent to which hypotheses are perceived as plausible (Klahr et al.,

    1993), and the way evidence is interpreted and evaluated (see, e.g.,

    Chinn & Brewer, 1993). Specifically, Klaczynski (2000) found

    that although adolescents used higher order analytic reasoning to

    evaluate evidence that was inconsistent with their beliefs, they

    relied on simple heuristics to evaluate evidence that was consis-

    tent. We reasoned, therefore, that favoring one alternative belief

    might influence decisions concerning the extent to which its va-

    lidity could be tested and, more importantly, proposals concerning

    the way it could be tested. To control for possible prior beliefbiases in the present study, half of all the disagreements involved

    one alternative hypothesis or preference that students had been

    found to favor, whereas the other half involved neutral

    alternatives.

    To summarize, the primary goal of the present study was to

    determine the extent to which elementary school children distin-

    guished hypotheses from preferences as belief statements whose

    truth value can be determined and to examine the kinds of tests that

    they proposed. We hypothesized that older children would be more

    likely than younger children (a) to indicate that only hypotheses, as

    opposed to preferences, could be tested and (b) to propose empir-

    ical tests, although not necessarily well designed or correct, as

    opposed to subjective evaluations or references to authority. An

    additional but secondary goal was to examine the extent to which

    younger and older children were influenced by their prior belief

    biases in their decisions and test proposals.

    Method

    Participants and Procedure

    The participants in the study were 60 students who came from predom-

    inantly middle-class backgrounds and whose native language was Greek.

    All students were attending the same elementary school located in a large

    metropolitan area in the island nation of Cyprus. Half of the students ( n

    30) were attending Grade 2 (15 boys and 15 girls), and their ages ranged

    from 7 years 6 months to 8 years 3 months (mean age 7 years 11

    months). The rest of the students (n 30) were attending Grade 6 (17 boys

    and 13 girls), and their ages ranged from 11 years 3 months to 12 years 4

    months (mean age 11 years 7 months). All participants came from one

    second-grade classroom and one sixth-grade classroom chosen randomly

    from the three classrooms per grade level available at the school. Grade

    point averages and individual subject test scores were not made available

    as a matter of school policy. However, at the time of the study, the school

    had an explicit mixed-ability grouping policy, and therefore, it is morelikely that a range of school achievement levels was represented in the

    sample.

    All students were interviewed individually twice by Christos Ioannides,

    an experienced science educator, and his research assistant. Both inter-

    views took place during the school day and were conducted in the students

    and the researchers native language. At the beginning of the first inter-

    view, each student was informed about the general purpose of the study and

    the types of questions that he or she would be asked. The first interview

    took place after the student had indicated his or her willingness to continue

    and lasted approximately 5 min. Its purpose was to reveal students

    personal preferences about foods and colors and their prior beliefs con-

    cerning the properties of these. The second interview took place 3 days

    later and lasted approximately 10 min. Its purpose was to reveal students

    understanding of hypotheses as distinct from preferences. All responses

    were tape-recorded and transcribed.

    Materials

    Preliminary questionnaire. The first interview was structured accord-

    ing to a preliminary questionnaire that included 12 questions. Half of the

    questions were designed to elicit students preferences about foods and

    colors. Specifically, students were asked to name foods and colors they

    liked best, those they disliked, and those they neither liked nor disliked.

    The rest of the questions were designed to elicit students personal beliefs

    about specific properties of foods and colors that could potentially function

    as hypotheses. Specifically, students were asked to name foods they

    believed had high nutritional value, foods they believed had low nutritional

    value, and foods whose nutritional value they believed was average.

    Similarly, students were asked to name colors they believed were highly

    visible from a long distance away, colors they believed were not visible,

    and colors whose visibility they believed was about average.

    Main questionnaire. The second interview was structured according to

    a main questionnaire that included eight disagreement scenarios or cases,

    each followed by a question and a justification requirement (see Appen-

    dix). Students were asked to consider each disagreement case, to evaluate

    whether it would be possible to decide if one side or party was right, and

    to justify their answer. Overall, half of all the cases concerned disagree-

    ments about foods, whereas the rest concerned disagreements about colors.

    Moreover, half of the cases referred to disagreements about matters of

    preference (Cases 1, 2, 5, and 6; see Appendix), whereas the rest referred

    to disagreements about beliefs that could function as hypotheses (Cases 3,

    4, 7, and 8; see Appendix).

    The main questionnaire was individualized according to each students

    personal beliefs, as indicated by his or her responses to the preliminaryquestionnaire. Each student had to consider disagreements for which he or

    she was found to share the preference or hypothetical belief expressed by

    one party and disagreements for which the student had previously ex-

    pressed no strong bias. As a result, the main questionnaire included two

    biased preference cases (Cases 1 and 5; see Appendix), two neutral

    preference cases (Cases 2 and 6; see Appendix), two biased belief cases

    (Cases 3 and 7; see Appendix), and two neutral belief cases (Cases 4 and

    8; see Appendix). The order of question presentation was counterbalanced

    between students both with respect to conceptual category (foods and

    colors) and with respect to within-category questions.

    Students responses to the questions following each disagreement case

    were scored as to their appropriateness depending on whether the case

    reflected a disagreement in preference or hypothetical belief. For example,

    indications that the nutritional value of foods and the visibility of colors

    538 DIAKIDOY AND IOANNIDES

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    4/9

    could be determined would constitute appropriate responses. On the other

    hand, indications that the tastiness of foods and the beauty of colors could

    also be determined would constitute inappropriate responses. Appropriate

    responses received a score of 1, and inappropriate responses received a

    score of 0. Subsequently, Christos Ioannides and his research assistant,

    independently of each other, classified responses and justifications into

    categories designed to capture the full range of the responses obtained.

    Interrater agreement was high (84%), and all differences were resolved byIrene-Anna N. Diakidoy.

    Results

    Differentiating Between Hypotheses and Preferences

    Preliminary analysis indicated that scores received for all cases

    within each conceptual category (food and color) were not signif-

    icantly different from each other (M 2.53, SD 0.90, andM

    2.70, SD 0.91, respectively), paired t(57) 1.31, p .19

    (two-tailed), d 0.21. Therefore, students scores across cases

    were summed to yield six combined scores: a total belief score, a

    total preference score, a biased belief score, a biased preference

    score, a neutral belief score, and a neutral preference score. How-ever, the small number of cases within each score category and the

    near-ceiling performance on the belief cases resulted in marked

    deviations from normality (see Table 1). Therefore, data were

    analyzed with nonparametric procedures, and effect sizes were

    estimated on the basis of proportion differences (Fleiss, 1994).

    Overall, 35 students (59%) recognized correctly that the validity of

    hypothetical beliefs can be determined, 2(4,N 60) 61.42,p

    .00, whereas 18 students (31%) indicated incorrectly that the validity

    of personal preferences can also be determined, 2(4, N 60)

    14.31,p .01,D 0.28. Moreover, it can be seen from Table 2 that

    correct and incorrect responses were equally frequent in the prefer-

    ence categories. A Wilcoxon signed-ranks test for matched pairs

    showed that differences between beliefs and preferences, in terms of

    correct responses, were significant, Z 3.60,p .00 (two-tailed),

    with effect sizes ranging from D 0.20 to D 0.48. Although

    response patterns in the biased belief and neutral belief categories

    were significantly different from each other, Z 3.35, p .00

    (two-tailed), with effect sizes ranging from D 0.14 toD 0.22,

    this was not the case with the biased preference and neutral preference

    categories,Z 1.36,p .17 (two-tailed).

    A series of Mann-Whitney tests indicated that response patterns

    in any of the categories were not significantly different as a

    function of sex (p .05). On the other hand, differences as a

    function of grade emerged as significant only with respect to the

    preference categories (see Table 3). Second graders (37%) were

    more likely than sixth graders (24%) to indicate incorrectly that the

    truth value of preferences can also be determined,Z 2.41,p

    .02 (two-tailed), D 0.13. Moreover, there were significant dif-

    ferences in the sixth gradersresponse patterns in the biased belief

    and neutral belief categories, Z 2.80, p .01 (two-tailed),

    with effect sizes ranging from D 0.10 to D 0.26. In compar-

    ison, response differences between biased belief and neutral beliefcategories were not as pronounced in the second graders group,

    Z 1.96, p .05 (two-tailed). However, students at both grade

    levels had similar response patterns in the biased preference and

    neutral preference categories (p .05).

    Justification Categories

    Tables 4 and 5 show the types of justification given by students

    for their positive and negative responses and their frequency in

    each of the belief and preference cases. Overall, it can be seen that

    the frequency of unjustified responses (9% on average) and simple

    belief restatements (4% on average) was low across all cases of

    disagreement. With respect to statements of preference (see Table

    4), justifications on the basis of subjective evaluations that couldnot lead to generalizable conclusions were the most prevalent

    (38% on average). A typical example of this justification type was

    given by Constantinos (Grade 2), who indicated that yes, each

    one should try the others favorite food, and then they will see who

    is right [about which food tastes better].In fact, all students who

    resorted to this type of justification stated that simply tasting the

    foods or painting the colors would help them resolve the disagree-

    Table 3

    Score Frequencies in Biased and Neutral Categories Within Grade

    Category

    Score

    2 N0 1 2

    Grade 2Biased belief 2 5 22 24.07** 29Neutral belief 4 8 17 9.17* 29Biased preference 15 9 6 4.20 30Neutral preference 14 10 6 3.20 30

    Grade 6Biased belief 0 4 26 16.13** 30Neutral belief 3 9 18 11.40** 30Biased preference 9 7 14 2.60 30Neutral preference 7 5 17 8.55* 29

    Note. The degrees of freedom for all chi-square tests are 2.*p .05. **p .01.

    Table 1

    Means, Standard Deviations, and Normality Indices for

    Combined Scores (N 60)

    Combined scores M SD Kurtosis Skewness

    Biased belief 1.78 0.49 4.40 2.23Neutral belief 1.48 0.70 0.30 0.98

    Total belief 3.25 1.08 0.68 1.31Biased preference 0.93 0.86 1.65 0.13Neutral preference 1.03 0.87 1.69 0.07

    Total preference 1.97 1.67 1.64 0.08

    Note. Maximum possible biased and neutral scores 2. Maximumpossible total score 4.

    Table 2

    Score Frequencies in Biased and Neutral Categories

    Category

    Score

    2 N0 1 2

    Biased belief 2 9 48 62.47** 59Neutral belief 7 17 35 20.47** 59Biased preference 24 16 20 1.60 60Neutral preference 21 15 23 1.76 59

    Note. The degrees of freedom for all chi-square tests are 2.**p .01.

    539DIFFERENTIATING HYPOTHESES FROM PREFERENCES

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    5/9

    ment. On the other hand, negative answers justified on the basis of

    individual differences, which would also be more appropriate for

    statements of personal preference, were less frequent (28% on

    average). For example, Aphrodite (Grade 6) decided that no, we

    cannot [determine who is right], because it depends on what color

    each one likes.Moreover, about 15% of all students justified their

    negative answers by resorting to egalitarian responses. An example

    of such a response was given by Christos (Grade 6), who said that

    we cannot say [who is right], because both colors are nice.The

    frequency of egalitarian responses was comparable across cases ofbiased preference and neutral preference. Finally, it is interesting

    to note that a few students (5% on average) justified their positive

    responses by proposing an objective evaluation of a different but

    related belief statement. Phanis (Grade 6), for example, proposed

    that the two parties should paint one sheet green and another

    yellow and then have their classmates vote which one is more

    beautiful.

    With respect to statements of belief that could function as

    hypotheses (see Table 5), justifications on the basis of objective

    evaluations were the most frequent (38% on average), especially

    for cases concerning the visibility of colors from a distance.

    Typically, these justifications involved looking from a distance.

    Maria (Grade 2), for example, indicated that, to determine which

    color is more visible from a distance, they should paint both on

    pieces of paper, then go far away and see which color can be seen

    better. The objective evaluations proposed in the case of the

    foods nutritional values were slightly more varied. For Cypriana

    (Grade 2), the way to determine which food is more nutritious was

    to have each party eat one kind of food and then see who gets

    fatter. For Michael (Grade 6), on the other hand, the way to

    determine which food is more nutritious was to have each party

    eat one kind of food only. Then, after a while, see which person

    has gained more weight. The person who has gained the most has

    eaten the least nutritious food.A few students thought that health,

    instead of growth, was the important indicator and, like Stephanos

    (Grade 6), stated that each one should have a blood testmaybe

    check for cholesterol? Finally, one student, Stelios (Grade 6),

    proposed thatwe can analyze the hamburger and see how many

    vitamins and other nutrition stuff it has. Then we can do the same

    with corn flakes and compare them.Justifications on the basis of

    objective evaluations, regardless of their completeness or scientific

    adequacy, were considered to be the most appropriate for cases of

    belief. However, several students (14% on average) also proposedsubjective evaluations similar to the ones proposed for cases of

    preference.

    Students also justified their positive responses with references to

    properties of foods and colors or to objects having a particular

    color (11% on average) and with references to authority, such as

    parents, doctors, and favorite friends (8% on average). For exam-

    ple, Marina (Grade 6) decided that one party was wrong because

    potatoes do not have as many vitamins as beans. Antonis (Grade

    6) determined that yellow must be more visible from a distance

    because the sun is yellow and it is far away.Natasha (Grade 2),

    on the other hand, suggested that they should ask their mothers,

    and then they will see who is right. It must be noted that

    references to properties, objects, and authorities were more fre-

    quent in cases of disagreement about the nutritional value of foods

    than in cases concerning the visibility of colors (see Table 5).

    Finally, egalitarian responses were more frequent in cases of

    neutral belief (15% on average) than in cases of biased belief (5%

    on average).

    Justification categories were not equally frequent across grade

    levels. Unjustified responses and belief restatements were more

    frequent in Grade 2 (19% on average) than in Grade 6 (6% on

    average). With respect to preference cases (biased or neutral), the

    younger students were more likely to justify their responses on the

    basis of subjective evaluations (46% on average), whereas sixth

    graders were more likely to suggest that disagreements were due to

    individual differences (51% on average). Moreover, the second

    most frequent justification type for the second graders was theegalitarian response (21% on average), whereas for the sixth

    graders, it was the subjective evaluation (26% on average). Dif-

    Table 5

    Frequency of Justification Categories in Cases of Biased Belief

    and Neutral Belief (N 60)

    Justification category

    Biased belief Neutral belief

    Case 3 Case 7 Case 4 Case 8

    Yes

    No explanation 3 1 0 1No way to find out 4 1 1 3Belief restatement 3 4 2 3Reference to authority 10 0 9 0Reference to property

    or object 14 2 5 4Subjective evaluation 9 8 11 6Objective evaluation of

    related belief 0 0 1 0Objective evaluation 12 36 9 34

    NoNo explanation 1 2 5 2Egalitarian responses 2 4 13 5Reference to individual

    differences 1 2 2 2Dont know/no response 1 0 2 0

    Table 4

    Frequency of Justification Categories in Cases of Biased

    Preference and Neutral Preference (N 60)

    Justification category

    Biased preference Neutral preference

    Case 1 Case 5 Case 2 Case 6

    YesNo explanation 1 1 0 1No way to find out 0 4 2 1Belief restatement 1 0 3 2Reference to authority 0 2 1 2Reference to property

    or object 1 2 1 2Subjective evaluation 28 19 25 18Objective evaluation of

    related belief 2 5 1 3Objective evaluation 0 0 0 0

    NoNo explanation 3 0 2 2Egalitarian responses 8 10 8 9Reference to individual

    differences 15 17 17 19Dont know/no response 1 0 0 1

    540 DIAKIDOY AND IOANNIDES

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    6/9

    ferences between grade levels were not as clear with respect to the

    belief cases. Although the older students were more likely to

    propose objective evaluations (48% on average), they also resorted

    to references to properties and authorities when considering the

    nutritional value of foods (23% on average). In contrast, the

    younger students proposed objective evaluations primarily when

    considering the visibility of colors (47% on average). Otherwise,they were more likely to propose subjective evaluations (23% on

    average). Finally, egalitarian responses were given by both the

    second graders (17% on average) and the sixth graders (23% on

    average) only to neutral belief cases.

    Discussion

    Distinguishing Hypotheses From Preferences

    The first question that motivated this study was whether

    younger and older elementary school children distinguish hypoth-

    eses as beliefs whose validity can be tested from preferences that

    are justifiably variable. The findings indicate that, whereas stu-

    dents readily agreed that the validity of hypotheses can be deter-

    mined, they had difficulty understanding that the same is not true

    for statements of preference. As expected, however, older children

    were more likely to consider preferences as legitimately variable

    and to attribute them to individual differences. In contrast, younger

    children were likely to think that disagreements about preference

    could also be resolved in favor of one side, and they proposed

    evaluations that by necessity involved subjective comparisons that

    would not yield generalizable conclusions. These findings suggest

    that younger children (7- to 8-year-olds) have difficulty differen-

    tiating between hypotheses and preferences. Older children (11- to

    12-year-olds), on the other hand, appear to be better able to

    distinguish between hypotheses and preferences, but the relatively

    small effect size indicates that they do not do so with accuracy.These findings appear to be in contrast to those of the Carpen-

    dale and Chandler (1996) study, which showed that all 5- to

    8-year-old children tended to consider differences in preference as

    more acceptable than differences in the interpretation of ambigu-

    ous stimuli. The fact, however, that a difference in preference is

    considered acceptable does not necessarily imply an understanding

    that it is not resolvable (see also Flavell, Flavell, Green, & Moses,

    1990). The present findings lend validity to the above claim.

    Although we did not ask children to decide whether it was okay for

    two people to disagree (as in Carpendale & Chandler, 1996), we

    can assume that they also considered disagreements acceptable,

    even if only in the sense that they recognized that different people

    can believe different things. However, the majority of the younger

    children and some of the older ones believed also that disagree-

    ments can be resolved regardless of whether they involve differ-

    ences in preferences or hypotheses. Moreover, the way they pro-

    posed this could be done was similar for both kinds of belief

    statementsthat is, by directing attention outward, toward the

    stimuli in question (comparing foods and colors), rather than

    inward, as Flavell et al. (1990) had claimed to be the case with

    preferences and as Carpendale and Chandler (1996) had found to

    be the case with the older children in their sample. These findings

    appear to suggest that the metaconceptual ability that would allow

    a reflection on and a further differentiation between the kinds of

    beliefs that one may have is either lacking or not consistently

    manifested in the early elementary school years.

    The tendency to consider preferences and hypotheses as simi-

    larly testable can also be taken to reflect an epistemological

    presupposition that all statements can be either right or wrong. To

    the extent that beliefs and knowledge are justified similarly in the

    minds of students (Southerland et al., 2001), such a presupposition

    can be thought of as related to a starting, commonsense episte-

    mology, according to which knowledge is certain and conflicts areattributable to incomplete or inaccurate information (Carey &

    Smith, 1993; Hofer & Pintrich, 1997). The possibilities of limited

    metaconceptual ability and a deterministic epistemological presup-

    position do not necessarily represent alternative interpretations of

    the findings. In fact, we consider them related in the sense that lack

    of reflection on ones own beliefs would help sustain a determin-

    istic outlook and that, in turn, a firm conviction that all beliefs can

    be right or wrong could inhibit such a reflection and, thereby,

    metaconceptual awareness.

    Older childrens increased ability to recognize that some belief

    statements are not testable may reflect increased metaconceptual

    understanding and a weakening deterministic epistemology, both

    of these brought about by their greater familiarity with the kinds of

    belief statements that drive scientific investigation. It must be

    noted, however, that the way science is taught in the Cypriot

    elementary school is more likely to reinforce, inadvertently, a less

    sophisticated, deterministic epistemological view. Science educa-

    tion content and outcomes are determined by a national curriculum

    (Cypriot Ministry of Education and Culture, 1996). All teachers

    are required to follow the instructional methods that are specified

    in detail for each lesson unitincluding presentation content, time

    frames, activities, teacher demonstrations, and questionsin the

    science teachers manual (Kyprianou, Loizidou, Charalambous,

    Matsikaris, & Yiannakis, 1997). According to the manual, lessons

    start with definitions and examples of target concepts. Subse-

    quently, students engage in classification and example-recognition

    activities. In addition, they observe teacher demonstrations orconduct prespecified miniexperiments, both of which serve to

    prove the validity of the previously offered accounts.

    Although the manual advises teachers to start each lesson by

    asking students what they know about the target concepts or the

    general topic, it offers no similarly explicit guidelines on how to

    respond to studentsideas or, in fact, whether to respond at all (see,

    e.g., Kyprianou et al., 1997). In this case, it is up to the individual

    teacher to decide whether to have students pursue their ideas

    further or to proceed with the lesson. The second option is more

    viable given the large amount of content that must be covered

    within specific lesson periods, as well as within the course of the

    school year (Cypriot Ministry of Education and Culture, 1996). As

    a result, the sixth graders in our sample had limited experience, if

    any, in formulating and investigating hypotheses in science (see,

    e.g., Chinn & Malhotra, 2002). Therefore, their increased ability to

    differentiate between kinds of belief, when compared with that of

    the younger students, may also simply reflect their greater expe-

    rience with unresolved preference disputes in the context of ev-

    eryday life.

    Although there was a tendency to regard hypotheses and pref-

    erences as similarly testable, prior belief bias was found to exert an

    influence on responses to hypothetical beliefs only. In general,

    students confidence that a disagreement could be resolved was

    greater when it involved a hypothetical belief that was favored as

    opposed to a neutral belief. A corresponding tendency was not

    evident in students responses concerning preferences. Moreover,

    541DIFFERENTIATING HYPOTHESES FROM PREFERENCES

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    7/9

    the influence of prior belief bias was greater in the older age group

    than in the younger age group. Although, one could speculate that

    such differential influences might reflect conceptual differentiation

    to some degree, we consider such a speculation as unwarranted

    given the modest effect sizes and the limited scope of the study

    with respect to this factor.

    Proposing Tests for Hypotheses

    The second question that the study sought to address concerned

    the extent to which students were able to propose objective,

    empirical tests for determining the validity of hypotheses. The

    findings indicate that although the older children were clearly

    better able to think of empirical tests, the younger children were

    also able to propose objective evaluations in some cases. More-

    over, all children were better able to think of empirical tests when

    considering the visibility of colors from a distance than when

    considering the nutritional value of different kinds of food. Be-

    cause of the current emphasis on health and nutrition, all students

    in the Cypriot elementary school have been advised at least once

    about the importance of a healthy diet. That, in turn, may explain

    the overall higher frequency of references to properties of food,

    such as vitamin and sugar content, and to authorities, such as

    doctors and dieticians, when considering the nutritional value of

    foods. In contrast, students everyday life provided many oppor-

    tunities for discovering and evaluating what things can be seen and

    from how far away (e.g., letters on the blackboard). Therefore,

    conceptual and task familiarity may have been responsible for all

    students increased ability to think of a test to resolve disagree-

    ments about the visibility of colors.

    In agreement with previous research (e.g., Sodian et al., 1991;

    Wimmer & Perner, 1983), our findings also indicate that young

    elementary school children demonstrate an understanding that a

    belief is justifiable on reasons or facts that are distinct from thebelief itself. Few children, even in the younger age group, failed to

    justify their responses, and even fewer restated a belief as evidence

    for its validity. Moreover, we would argue that failure to justify a

    belief does not necessarily reflect lack of understanding of what an

    external justification is and of its necessity. Evidence for this is

    provided by the few children in our sample who explicitly attrib-

    uted their inability to justify to the fact that they did not know of

    or they could not think of a way to evaluate who was right or

    wrong. Therefore, young childrens notable reliance on external

    justifications and evaluations (subjective or objective) necessarily

    implies that they also possess the basic ingredients of the strategic

    competence that, according to Kuhn (1997), is needed to under-

    stand the inferential relationship between evidence and belief.

    The objective evaluations that our sample proposed did not

    necessarily represent well-designed hypothesis tests, and in the

    case of nutritional values, they were often scientifically inaccurate.

    They were, however, genuine attempts to set up test conditions that

    could yield potentially useful evidence. On the other hand, sub-

    jective evaluations can also be taken to represent attempts at

    testing and, as expected, were more prevalent with personal pref-

    erence conflicts. It is also notable that the few students who

    proposed objective evaluations to resolve them did so by interpret-

    ing the initial statements as hypothetical generalizations about

    peoples preferences. This dominant tendency to propose some

    kind of test suggests that elementary school students have a basic

    understanding of experimentation (Sodian et al., 1991) even if they

    have not yet mastered the intricacies of the skill. We would further

    expect the acquisition and the successful application of this skill to

    go hand in hand with, if not to depend on, the ability to distinguish

    the kinds of belief statements that can be the focus of experimental

    investigation.

    Limitations and Suggestions for Further Research

    One could argue that our basic task requirement may have

    biased the students to answer in the affirmative and to do their best

    to propose some kind of test. Children may have responded dif-

    ferently in the cases of preference if we had asked them whether it

    could be determined if someone was right, instead of who was

    right. However, we consider this possibility less likely given the

    almost equal frequency of correct and incorrect responses in all

    cases of preference. On the other hand, it must be noted that our

    task was relatively limited when it came to revealing the full extent

    of students ability to think of empirical tests. It is possible that

    students who proposed objective tests would have been able to

    revise and develop their proposals further if they had been asked to

    elaborate them. Similarly, students who proposed subjective tests

    might have been able to recognize their proposalslack of potential

    to conclusively resolve a disagreement if they had been confronted

    with the issue. Future research could modify and extend the basic

    task to require children to consider the possible and expected

    results of their test proposals and the extent to which these would

    allow them to resolve a disagreement conclusively.

    Arguably, the beliefs that our sample had to consider repre-

    sented simple categorical statements. They were not beliefs about

    complex causal relationships of the type investigated by Kuhn

    (e.g., Kuhn et al., 2000). Therefore, one could suppose that chil-

    drens extensive experience with classifying the world might have

    better prepared them to deal with the contrasting beliefs that our

    tasks involved. It is possible that if we had asked them to considerdisagreements about factors influencing the nutritional value of

    foods or the visibility of colors, they might have resorted more

    often to belief restatements. To our knowledge, there is no research

    that has directly examined the extent to which young children s

    ability to differentiate hypotheses and to coordinate them with

    evidence varies as a function of the type of hypotheses. The

    contrasting findings of previous research (e.g., Kuhn et al., 1995;

    Sodian et al., 1991) suggest that this factor may also play a role.

    Therefore, further research in this direction may help to better

    describe and explain younger childrens ability to engage in sci-

    entific reasoning.

    Future research could also be designed to provide a more

    in-depth look at the influence of prior belief bias and conceptual

    familiarity on the ability to distinguish hypotheses from other

    beliefs and on the types of tests proposed. Although prior belief

    bias was included as a factor and was found to selectively influ-

    ence decisions concerning hypotheses only, the limited number of

    disagreement cases involving biased and neutral hypothetical be-

    liefs and preferences does not permit any definite conclusions to be

    drawn at this point. In contrast, there was no systematic effort to

    control for conceptual or task familiarity in this study. Neverthe-

    less, there were clear task differences with respect to the ability to

    think of objective hypothesis tests and that appeared to be due to

    conceptual familiarity differences. Therefore, a more thorough

    examination of this factor and its possible interaction with belief

    bias would provide a test of this possibility and would contribute

    542 DIAKIDOY AND IOANNIDES

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    8/9

    to arguments concerning the influence of prior knowledge in

    relation to domain-general heuristics in the development of scien-

    tific reasoning skills (see, e.g., Klahr et al., 1993).

    Conclusions and Implications

    The findings of the present study indicate that the related no-

    tions of belief justification and evaluation may be acquired earlier

    than, albeit to a limited degree, and more or less independently of

    the ability to distinguish between different kinds of beliefs. Nev-

    ertheless, elementary school childrens limited ability to distin-

    guish hypotheses from unverifiable belief statements is likely to

    interfere with their understanding of what a conclusive hypothesis

    test is all about and with their ability to formulate researchable

    questions in a scientific inquiry context. However, studentsinitial

    understandings of belief and belief justification can provide a

    fertile ground for subsequent conceptual differentiation, refine-

    ment, and extension. Early and extensive practice in formulating

    and evaluating their own beliefs should facilitate childrens ability

    to distinguish those that can be empirically and conclusively

    verified from those that cannot. This, in turn, should promote thedevelopment of the metacognitive and metastrategic competencies

    that Kuhn (1997) has claimed to be necessary for scientific rea-

    soning and increase the epistemological authenticity of scientific

    inquiry in educational settings (Chinn & Mahlotra, 2002; Smith,

    Maclin, Houghton, & Hennessey, 2000).

    References

    Carey, S., & Smith, C. (1993). On understanding the nature of scientific

    knowledge.Educational Psychologist, 28, 235251.

    Carpendale, J. I., & Chandler, M. J. (1996). On the distinction between

    false belief understanding and subscribing to an interpretive theory of

    mind.Child Development, 67, 1686 1706.

    Chinn, C. A., & Brewer, W. F. (1993). The role of anomalous data inknowledge acquisition: A theoretical framework and implications for

    science instruction. Review of Educational Research, 63, 1 49.

    Chinn, C. A., & Malhotra, B. A. (2002). Epistemologically authentic

    inquiry in schools: A theoretical framework for evaluating inquiry tasks.

    Science Education, 86, 175218.

    Cypriot Ministry of Education and Culture. (1996). Elementary education:

    National curriculum. Nicosia: Government of Cyprus.

    Dewey, J. (1906). Beliefs and realities.Philosophical Review, 15,113129.

    Dworkin, R. (1996). Objectivity and truth: Youd better believe it.Philos-

    ophy and Public Affairs, 25, 87139.

    Elby, A., & Hammer, D. (2001). On the substance of a sophisticated

    epistemology.Science Education, 85, 554 567.

    Flavell, J. H., Flavell, E. R., Green, F. L., & Moses, L. J. (1990). Young

    childrens understanding of fact beliefs versus value beliefs. Child

    Development, 61, 915928.Fleiss, J. L. (1994). Measures of effect size for categorical data. In H.

    Cooper & L. V. Hedges (Eds.), The handbook of research synthesis(pp.

    245260). New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Guzzetti, B. J., Snyder, T. E., Glass, G. V., & Gamas, W. S. (1993).

    Promoting conceptual change in science: A comparative meta-analysis

    of instructional interventions from reading education and science edu-

    cation.Reading Research Quarterly, 28, 116 159.

    Hofer, B. K., & Pintrich, P. R. (1997). The development of epistemological

    theories: Beliefs about knowledge and knowing and their relation to

    learning. Review of Educational Research, 67, 88 140.

    Ioannides, C., & Vosniadou, S. (2002). The changing meanings of force.

    Cognitive Science Quarterly, 2, 5 62.

    Klaczynski, P. A. (2000). Motivated scientific reasoning biases, epistemo-logical beliefs, and theory polarization: A two-process approach to

    adolescent cognition. Child Development, 71, 13471366.

    Klahr, D., Fay, A. L., & Dunbar, K. (1993). Heuristics for scientific

    experimentation: A developmental study. Cognitive Psychology, 25,

    111146.

    Kuhn, D. (1997). Constraints or guideposts? Developmental psychology

    and science education. Review of Educational Research, 67, 141150.

    Kuhn, D., Amsel, E., & OLoughlin, M. (1988). The development of

    scientific thinking skills. New York: Academic Press.

    Kuhn, D., Black, J., Keselman, A., & Kaplan, D. (2000). The development

    of cognitive skills to support inquiry learning.Cognition and Instruction,

    18, 495523.

    Kuhn, D., Garcia-Mila, M., Zohar, A., & Andersen, C. (1995). Strategies

    of knowledge acquisition. Monographs of the Society for Research in

    Child Development, 60(4, Serial No. 245).

    Kyprianou, K., Loizidou, P., Charalambous, P., Matsikaris, G., & Yianna-

    kis, I. (1997). First steps in science: Sixth-grade science teachers

    manual.Nicosia: Government of Cyprus.

    McGinn, M. K., & Roth, W. M. (1999). Preparing students for competent

    scientific practice: Implications of recent research in science and tech-

    nology studies. Educational Researcher, 28(3), 14 24.

    Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge,

    MA: MIT Press.

    Polanyi, M. (1950). Scientific beliefs. Ethics, 61, 2737.

    Smith, C., Maclin, D., Grosslight, L., & Davis, H. (1997). Teaching for

    understanding: A study of studentspreinstruction theories of matter and

    a comparison of the effectiveness of two approaches to teaching about

    matter and density. Cognition and Instruction, 15, 317393.

    Smith, C., Maclin, D., Houghton, C., & Hennessey, M. G. (2000). Sixth-grade studentsepistemologies of science: The impact of school science

    experiences on epistemological development.Cognition and Instruction,

    18, 349 422.

    Sodian, B., Zaitchik, D., & Carey, S. (1991). Young children s differenti-

    ation of hypothetical beliefs from evidence. Child Development, 62,

    753766.

    Southerland, S. A., Sinatra, G. M., & Matthews, M. R. (2001). Belief,

    knowledge, and science education. Educational Psychology Review, 13,

    325351.

    Stace, W. T. (1945). The problem of unreasoned beliefs.Mind, 54, 27 49.

    Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (1997). Reasoning independently of prior

    belief and individual differences in actively open-minded thinking.Jour-

    nal of Educational Psychology, 89, 342357.

    Toth, E. E., Klahr, D., & Chen, Z. (2000). Bridging research and practice:

    A cognitively based classroom intervention for teaching experimentationskills to elementary school children. Cognition and Instruction, 18,

    423 459.

    Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and

    constraining function of wrong beliefs in young childrens understand-

    ing of deception. Cognition, 13, 103128.

    (Appendix follows)

    543DIFFERENTIATING HYPOTHESES FROM PREFERENCES

  • 8/12/2019 School Childrens Ability to Distinguish Hypothetical Beliefs

    9/9

    Appendix

    Main Questionnaire

    Case 1

    George and Michael disagree about which food tastes better. George

    says that X (students favorite food) tastes better than Y (the student

    dislikes it). Michael says that Y tastes better than X.

    Question 1: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?

    If no, why not?

    Case 2

    Peter and Paul disagree about which food tastes better. Peter says that X

    tastes better than Y. Paul says that Y tastes better than X (student is

    indifferent to both foods).

    Question 2: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?

    If no, why not?

    Case 3

    Helen and Angela disagree about which food is more nutritious. Helen

    says that X (student considers it very nutritious) is more nutritious than Y

    (a food the student considers to be less nutritious). Angela says that Y is

    more nutritious than X.

    Question 3: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?

    If no, why not?

    Case 4

    Mary and Silvia disagree about which food is more nutritious. Mary says

    that X is more nutritious than Y. Silvia says that Y is more nutritious than

    X (student believes that both foods are equally nutritious).

    Question 4: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?

    If no, why not?

    Case 5

    Lucia and Georgia disagree about which color is more beautiful. Lucia

    says that X (students favorite color) is more beautiful than Y (student does

    not like it). Georgia says that Y is more beautiful than X.

    Question 5: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?

    If no, why not?

    Case 6

    Kostas and Lazaros disagree about which color is more beautiful. Kostas

    says that X is more beautiful than Y. Lazaros says that Y is more beautiful

    than X (student is indifferent to both colors).

    Question 6: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?

    If no, why not?

    Case 7

    Marina and Sofia disagree about which color can be seen from a longer

    distance. Marina says that X (the student considers it most visible) can beseen from a longer distance than Y (student considers it less visible from

    a distance). Sofia says that Y can be seen from a longer distance than X.

    Question 7: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?

    If no, why not?

    Case 8

    Paul and Nikolas disagree about which color can be seen from a longer

    distance. Paul says that X can be seen from a longer distance than Y.

    Nikolas says that Y can be seen from a longer distance than X (student

    believes that both colors are equally visible).

    Question 8: Can we determine who is right and who is wrong?

    If yes, how?If no, why not?

    Received February 3, 2003

    Revision received January 29, 2004

    Accepted February 10, 2004

    544 DIAKIDOY AND IOANNIDES