sociology of knowledge - coser

24
SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE by LEWIS A. COSER International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences Edited by David L. Sills. The Macmillan Co & The Free Press, NY, 1968 Vol. 7, pp. 428-434 The sociology of knowledge may be broadly defined as that branch of sociology which studies the relation between thought and society. It is concerned with the social or existential conditions of knowledge. Scholars in this field, far from being restricted to the sociological analysis of the cognitive sphere as the term would seem to imply, have concerned themselves with practically the entire range of intellectual products - philosophies and ideologies, political doctrines, and theological thought. In all these areas the sociology of knowledge attempts to relate the ideas it studies to the sociohistorical settings in which they are produced and received. Assertions as to how social structures are functionally related to categories of thought and to specific sets of ideas have a long history. At the be ginning of the seventeenth century, Francis Bacon outlined the general territory when he wrote about impressions of nature, which are imposed upon the mind by the sex, by the age, by the region, by health and sickness, by beauty and deformity, and the like, which are inherent and not extern; and again, those which are caused by extern fortune; as sovereignty nobility, obscure birth, riches, want, magistracy, privateness, prosperity, adversity, constant fortune, variable fortune, rising per saltum. per gradus, and the like. ([1605] 1958, p. 170) 1

Upload: catriel-fierro

Post on 21-Jul-2016

12 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE

by LEWIS A. COSER

International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences

Edited by David L. Sills. The Macmillan Co & The Free Press, NY, 1968 Vol. 7, pp. 428-434

The sociology of knowledge may be broadly defined as that branch of sociology which

studies the relation between thought and society. It is concerned with the social or existential

conditions of knowledge. Scholars in this field, far from being restricted to the sociological

analysis of the cognitive sphere as the term would seem to imply, have concerned themselves

with practically the entire range of intellectual products - philosophies and ideologies,

political doctrines, and theological thought. In all these areas the sociology of knowledge

attempts to relate the ideas it studies to the sociohistorical settings in which they are produced

and received.

Assertions as to how social structures are functionally related to categories of thought and to

specific sets of ideas have a long history. At the be ginning of the seventeenth century,

Francis Bacon outlined the general territory when he wrote about

impressions of nature, which are imposed upon the mind by the sex, by the age, by the region, by

health and sickness, by beauty and deformity, and the like, which are inherent and not extern; and

again, those which are caused by extern fortune; as sovereignty nobility, obscure birth, riches, want,

magistracy, privateness, prosperity, adversity, constant fortune, variable fortune, rising per saltum.

per gradus, and the like. ([1605] 1958, p. 170)

This is indeed the field that later systematic sociology of knowledge claimed as its province.

A variety of European thinkers of the seventeenth, eighteenth, and early nineteenth centuries

may be considered among the precursors of the sociology of knowledge. Several of the

philosophes of the Enlightenment (Condorcet in particular) inquired about the social

preconditions of different types of knowledge, and Auguste Comte's famous "law of three

stages"' asserting the intimate relationship between types of social structures and types of

knowledge, might well be considered a contribution to the sociology of knowledge. It

nevertheless remains true that systematic development of the sociology of knowledge as an

autonomous enterprise rather than as a by-product of other types of inquiry received its main

impetus from two trends in nineteenth-century European sociological thought: the Marxian

tradition in Germany and the Durkheimian tradition in France. Although neither these two

mainstreams - nor their tributaries - are by any means identical in their fundamental

1

Page 2: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

assumptions, they are the starting point of most theorizing in the field.

Marx and the German tradition

In his attempt to dissociate himself from the panlogical system of his former master, Hegel,

as well as from the "critical philosophy" of his former "young Hegelian" friends, Karl Marx

undertook, in some of his earlier writings, to establish a connection between philosophies and

the concrete social structures in which they emerged. "It has not occurred to any of these

philosophers," wrote Marx in The German Ideology, "to inquire into the connection of

German philosophy with German reality, the relation of their criticism to their own material

surroundings" (Marx & Engels [1845-1846] 1939, p. 6). This programmatic orientation once

established, Marx proceeded to analyze the ways in which systems of ideas appeared to

depend on the social positions - particularly the class positions - of their proponents.

In his struggle against the dominant ideas of his time Marx was led to a resolute

relativization of these ideas. The eternal verities of dominant thought appeared upon

analysis to be but the direct or indirect expression of the class interests of their exponents.

Marx attempted to explain ideas sytematically in terms of their functions and to relate the the

thought of individuals to their social roles and class positions: "The mode of production in

material life determines the general character of the social, political and spiritual processes of

life. it is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but on the contrary

their social existence determines their consciousness" ([1859] 1913, PP 11-12). While Marx

was mainly concerned with uncovering the relationships between bourgeois ideas and

bourgeois interests and life styles, he nevertheless explicitly stated that the same relation also

held true with regard to the emergence of new dissident and revolutionary ideas. According to

the Communist Manifesto,

What else does the history of ideas prove, than that Intellectual production changes its character in

proportion as material production is changed? The ruling ideas of each age have ever been the ideas

of its ruling klass. When people speak of ideas that revolutionize society, they do but express the fact

that within the old society the elements of a new one have been created, and that the dissolution of the

old ideas keeps even pace with the dissolution of the old conditions of existence. (Marx & Engels

1848. p. 91 in 1964 paperback edition)

In their writings of a later period, Marx and Engels were to qualify their somewhat sweeping

initial statements, which had most often been made in a polemical context. They were thus led

to grant a certain degree of intrinsic autonomy to the development of legal, political, religious,

literary, and artistic ideas. They now stressed that mathematics and the natural sciences were

exempt from the direct influence of the social and economic infrastructure. Moreover, they

2

Page 3: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

now granted that the intellectual superstructure of a society was not simply a reflection of the

infrastructure but rather could in turn react upon it.

While the original Marxian thesis reinterpreted in this fashion became a considerably more

flexible instrument, it also lost some of its distinctive qualities. Interpreted rigidly, it tended to

lend itself to use as a rather crude tool for debunking all adverse thought; interpreted flexibly,

it became difficult to distinguish from non-Marxian attempts at the functional analysis of

thought. Also, as Merton has pointed out ([1949] 1957, p. 479), when the Marxian thesis is

stated in so flexible a manner, it becomes impossible to invalidate it at all, since any set of

data may be so interpreted as to fit it.

Despite these difficulties, Marxian modes of analysis in this field, as in so many others,

exerted a powerful - if often subterranean - influence on subsequent German social thought.

Major portions of the work of Max Weber can be seen as attempts on the part of this greatest

of all German sociologists to come to terms with the Marxian inheritance and particularly

with the Marxian assertion of the essentially epiphenomenal character of knowledge and

ideas. The twin heritage of Marx and of Nietzsche (particularly the latter's "debunking" attack

on Christianity as a slave philosophy of ressentimen-laden lower-status groups) loomed very

large in the mental climate of pre-World War I Germany. But it remained for two German

scholars, Max Scheler and Karl Mannheim, to develop a corpus of theory that represents the

first systematic elaboration of the sociology of knowledge as a new scientific discipline. Even

though it followed upon the work of Max Scheler. Karl Mannheim's contribution will be dealt

with first, since it is more directly tied to the main themes of Marxian thought.

Mannheim and universal relativism. Mannheim undertook to generalize the Marxian

interpretation so as to divest it of polemical elements; thus he attempted to transform into a

general tool of analysis what for Marx had been primarily a means of attack against

adversaries. Mannheim wished to create a tool that could be used as effectively for the

analysis of Marxism as for any other system of thought. While in the Marxian formulations

attention was called to the function of ideology in the defense of class privileges and to the

distortions and falsifications of ideas that flowed from the privileged class position of

bourgeois thinkers, Marx's own ideas were held by Marxists to be true and unbiased by virtue

of their being an expression of classes that had no privileged interests to defend. According to

Marx, the defenders of the status quo were inevitably given to false consciousness, while their

critics, being affiliated with the emerging working class, were exempt from such distorting

influences and hence had access to "true consciousness" - that is, to nondistorted historical

truth. Mannheim's orientation, in contradistinction, allowed for the probability that all ideas,

3

Page 4: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

even "truths," were related to, and hence influenced by, the social and historical situation from

which they emerged. The very fact that each thinker is affiliated with particular groups in

society - that he occupies a certain status and enacts certain social roles - colors his

intellectual outlook. Men "do not confront the objects of the world from the abstract levels of

a contemplating mind as such, nor do they do so exclusively as solitary beings. On the

contrary they act with and against one another in diversely organized groups, and while doing

so they think with and against one another" (Mannheim [1929-1931] 1954, p. 3).

Mannheim was thus led to define the sociology of knowledge as a theory of the social or

existential conditioning of thought. To him all knowledge and all ideas, although to different

degrees, are "bound to a location" within the social structure and the historical process. At

particular times a particular group can have fuller access to the understanding of a social

phenomenon than other groups, but no group can have total access to it. (At times,

though, Mannheim expressed the hope that "detached intellectuals" might in our age achieve a

"unified"perspective" free of existential determination. ) The task of the new discipline was to

ascertain the empirical correlation between intellectual standpoints and structural and

historical positions. From its inception Mannheim's thesis encountered a great deal of

criticism, especially on the grounds that it led to universal relativism. It has been said that the

notion of relativism or relation-ism - the term that Mannheim preferred - "is self-

contradictory, for it must presuppose its own absoluteness. The sociology of knowledge ...

must assume its own validity if it is to have any meaning” (Dahlke 1940, p. 87). If it is

assumed that all thought is existentially determined and hence all truth but relative,

Mannheim's own thought cannot claim privileged exemption.

Mannheim did indeed lay himself open to such attacks, especially in his earlier writings;

however, it seems that he did not mean to imply that "existential determination"

(Seinsverbundenheif) is a kind of total determination that leaves no room for an examination

of ideas in other terms. He explicitly stated that in the social sciences, as elsewhere, "the

ultimate criterion of truth or falsity is to be found in the investigation of the object, and the

sociology of knowledge is no substitute for this" ([1929-1931] 1954, p. 4). No matter what

the imprecisions and methodological shortcomings of Mannheim's theoretical statements are

judged to be, he left a number of concrete studies on such topics as "Conservative Thought"

([1922-1940] 1953, pp. 77-164) and "Competition as a Cultural Phenomenon" ([1923-

1929] 1952, pp. 191-229) which have been recognized as important contributions even by

those who have been critical of Mannheim's theoretical apparatus.

Scheler's "real factors." Marx laid primary stress on economic and class factors in the

4

Page 5: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

determination of ideas; Mannheim expanded this conception to include other groupings such

as generations, status groups, and occupational groups. Max Scheler went still further in

widening the range of factors that influence thought forms. According to Scheler there is no

constant independent variable that determines the emergence of ideas; but rather, in the course

of history, there occurs a sequence of "real factors" that condition thought. In nonliteraic

groups, blood and kinship ties constitute the independent variable; later, political factors; and,

finally, in the modern world economic factors are to be considered as the independent

variables to which thought structures have to be related.

Scheler rejected what he considered the "naturalism" and relativism of previous theorizing in

the field and asserted that there exists an atemporal absolute order of values and ideas - that is,

a realm of eternal essences, which is totally distinct from historical and social reality. At

different moments in historical time and in different cultural systems, different "real factors»

predominate. These real factors "open and close, in determinate ways and determinate order,

the sluice gates of the stream of thought," so that different aspects of the eternal realm of

essences can be grasped at particular points in time and in particular cultural systems (1926).

Thus Scheler thought that he had succeeded in reconciling sociocultural relativity with the

Platonic notion of an eternal realm of unchanging essences.

Scheler's theory of eternal essences is metaphysical and hence not susceptible to scientific

validation. However, his proposal to widen the range of existential factors that may be seen as

the source of particular systems of ideas is testable and potentially fruitful for research.

Scheler's own studies provide important examples of the fruitfulness of this type of inquiry:

for example, his studies on the interrelations between the hierarchical medieval world of

communal estates and the medieval con-ception of the world as a hierarchy culminating to

God, between the content of Plato's theory of ideal and the formal organization of the Platonic

Academy, and between the rise of mechanistic models of thought and the rise of bourgeois,

Gesellschaft types of society. (For a different view of Schelez see Ranulf 1938.)

French contributions

Emile Durkheim's contributions to the sociology of knowledge form only a relatively small

part his total work. Although some of his statements this area are mixed with epistemological

speculations that most experts would consider rather dubious, he nevertheless did some of the

most vital pioneering work in the field. In his attempt to establish the social origin and

functions of morals, values, and religion, and in explaining these as different forms of

"collective representations," Durkheim was led to consider a similar social explanation of the

basic forms of logical classification and of the fundamental categories of thought themselves.

5

Page 6: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

Durkheim attempted to account: for the origins of spatial, temporal, and other classifications

among nonliterate peoples and concluded that these classifcations closely approximated the

social organization of these peoples (Durkheim & Mauss 1903). the first "classes," he

suggested, were classes of men, and the classification of objects in the world of nature was

but an extension of the social classifcation already established. All animals and natural objects

were classified as belonging to this or that clan, phratry, or residential or kinship group. Be

further argued that, although scientific classifications have now largely become divorced from

their social origins, the very manner in which we classify things as "belonging to the same

family" still reveals the originally social origins of classificatory thought.

In his last major book The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life (1912), Durkheim

returned to these earlier ideas and attempted a sociological explanation of all fundamental

categories of human thought, especially the concepts of time and space. These, he claimed,

are not only transmitted If society, they are social creations. Society is decisive in the genesis

of logical thought by forming the concepts of which that thought is made. The social

organization of the primitive community is the model for the primitive's spatial organization

of IBS surrounding world. Similarly, temporal divisions too days, weeks, months, and years

correspond to periodical recurrences of rites, leasts, and ceremonies: "A calendar expresses

the rhythm of the collective activities, while at the same time its function is to assure their

regularity" ([1912] 1954, p. 10).

These Durkheimian notions have been challenged frequently. It has been pointed out, for

example, that Durkheim slighted the importance of the rhythm of natural phenomena by his

overemphasis on social rhythms (Sorokin 1928, p. 477). More fundamentally, Claude Levi-

Strauss has argued that society "cannot exist without symbolism, instead of showing how the

appearance of thought makes social life altogether possible and necessary, Durkheim tries the

reverse, i.e., to make symbolism grow out of society. . . . Sociology cannot explain the genesis

of symbolic thought, but has just to take it for granted in man" (1945, p. 518).

Durkheim failed to establish the social origins of all categories of thought, but it is

important to recognize his pioneering contribution to the study of the correlations between

specific systems of thought and systems of social organization. It is this part of Durkheim's

contribution, rather than some of the more debatable epistemological propositions found in

his work, that has influenced later developments in the sociology of knowledge. Thus the

eminent Sinologist Marcel Granet (1934) used Durkheimian leads when he related the

conceptions of time and space in ancient Chinese thought to such social factors as the ancient

feudal organization and the rhythmic alterations of concentrated and dispersed group

6

Page 7: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

activities. Jane Harrison (1912) and Francis Cornford (1912) renovated classical studies by

tracing Greek religious notions and philosophical ideas to their origins in tribal initiation

ceremonies and to the clan structure of the Greek tribes. Finally. Maurice Halbwachs (1925)

attempted to establish how even such apparently private and intimate mental activities as

dreams and memories need for their organization a stable reference in the group life in which

individuals participate. [See DURKHEIM; GRANET; HALBWACHS.]

American sociology of knowledge

The work of the major American pragmatists - Pierce, James, and Dewey - abounds with

suggestive leads for the sociology of knowledge. To the extent that pragmatism stressed the

organic process by which every act of thought is linked to human conduct and thus rejected

the radical distinction between thinking and acting which had informed most classical

philosophy, it prepared the ground for consideration of the more specifically sociological

links between social conditions and the thought processes. Insofar as the pragmatists stressed

that thought is in its very nature bound to the social situation in which it arises, they set the

stage for efforts to inquire into the relations between a thinker and his audience. Insofar as

they rejected the traditional view according to which an object of thought was to be sharply

distinguished from the thinking subject and stressed the intimate transactions between subject

and object, they prepared the ground for the specifically American contributions to the

sociology of knowledge.

Pragmatic philosophy is not the only American intellectual trend to influence the development

of the sociology of knowledge. American historical scholarship, especially the work of

Charles A. Beard and Vernon L. Parrington, appropriated for its own uses a number of the

orientations of European sociology of knowledge - especially of its Marxian variety - in

efforts to develop new perspectives on American politics and letters by selfconsciously

relating currents of thought to economic interest and social condition. Many of these strains of

ideas had only an indirect impact on American sociology. In contrast, two major American

thinkers, Thorstein Veblen and George Herbert Mead, directly and explicitly influenced

American sociology of knowledge.

Veblen's emphasis on habits of thought as an outcome of habits of life and his stress on the

dependence of thought styles on community organization are well known. Perhaps less well

known is Veblen’s relatively systematic effort to relate styles of thought to the occupational

roles and positions of their proponents. "The scheme of thought or of knowledge," he wrote,

'is in good part a reverberation of the schemes of life" ([1891-1913] 1961. p. 105); hence,

those engaged in pecuniary occupations are likely to develop thought styles that differ from

7

Page 8: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

the styles of those engaged in industrial occupations. Magical as well as matter-of-fact ways

of thinking find their proponents among groups of men differentially located in the social

structure and in the economic process. Moreover, Veblen's savage polemics in his Higher

Learning in America (1918) should not be read as polemics alone. The work is also, and

perhaps above all, a seminal contribution to the sociological study of the organization and

functioning of the American university.

Finally, George Herbert Mead's social behaviorism, with its insistence that mind itself is a

social product and is of social origin, provided the social psychological basis for some of the

assertions of previous theorists. For Mead, communication was central to an understanding of

the nature of mind: "Mind arises through communication by a conversation of gestures in a

social process or context of experience" (1934, p. 50). Even when certain epistemological

positions of Mead are not accepted, it would seem very difficult to deny his claim that if

determinants of thought other than society itself exist, they can structure mind only

through the intermediary of the social relations in which it is necessarily enmeshed. [See

MEAD.]

Contemporary trends. As the sociology of knowledge has been incorporated into general

sociological theory both in America and in Europe, it has often merged with other areas of

research and is frequently no longer explicitly referred to as sociology of knowledge. Its

diffusion through partial incorporation has tended to make it lose some of its distinctive

characteristics. Thus, the works of Robert K. Merton (1949) and Bernard Barber (1952) in the

sociology of science, the works of E. C. Hughes (1958), T. H. Marshall ([1934-1949] 1950,

chapter 4), Theodore Caplow (1954), Oswald Hall (1948), Talcott Parsons (1938-1953), and

others in the sociology of the professions and occupations, and - even more generally - much

of the research concerned with social roles may be related to, and in part derived from, the

orientations of the sociology of knowledge. Many practitioners of what is in fact sociology of

knowledge may at times be rather surprised when it is pointed out that, like Monsieur

Jourdain, they have been "talking prose" all along.

Given this wide variety of research in which at least certain leads of the sociology of

knowledge have been utilized, it is difficult to delineate the distinctive characteristics of

contemporary or near contemporary developments in the sociology of knowledge in the

United States. Yet one characteristic seems salient. While in the European tradition attention

tended to be centered upon the production of ideas, with the axiomatic assumption that

different strata of society produce different types of ideas, modern American research is

more concerned with the consumption of ideas and the ways in which different strata of

8

Page 9: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

society use standardized thought products. To some extent, as Merton has pointed out ([1949]

1957, pp. 440 ff.), the sociology of public opinion and mass communication has pre-empted

the place of the sociology of knowledge in the contemporary United States.

Nevertheless, recent American contributions have by no means been limited to this field.

There has been a significant attempt at stocktaking and at discussing methodological

questions left unresolved by the European tradition. Merton's writings in this area represent

the most sophisticated codification of the problems faced by the sociology of knowledge.

Among other notable contributions to the methodology and theoretical clarification of the

sociology of knowledge are those of the philosopher Arthur Child and the sociologists

Hans Speier (1938), Gerald DeGre (1943), Kurt H. Wolff (1959), Werner Stark

(1958), and C. Wright Mills (1963).

Among substantive American contributions, the work of Pitirim A. Sorokin is of special

note (1937-1941; 1943). Blending an earlier European tradition of large-scale speculation

with American statistical research techniques, Sorokin developed a characteristically idealistic

theory of the sociology of knowledge. Rejecting the prevalent conceptualizations that

consider social classes or other social and economic groups as the independent variable in the

functional relations between thought and society. Sorokin considers variant "cultural

mentalities" or cultural premises as the key variables. He attempts to show that the periodic

dominance of three major cultural tendencies - the ideational, the idealistic, and the sensate

mentality - can account for the fluctuations of types of knowledge that have marked history.

Although his argument often seems to involve a kind of circular reasoning, and although the"

neglect of the existential roots of thought can hardly be justified in view of the promising

results already achieved by Sorokin's predecessors, the many contributions by Sorokin and

some of his students - in, for example, the sociology of science or the elucidation of the

notion of social time - remain noteworthy.

Florian Znaniecki's neglected but important study The Social Role of the Man of Knowledge

(1940) represents, like Sorokin's work, a fruitful blending of the European tradition with

American contributions. Znaniecki introduces the notion of the "social circle," that is, the

audience or public to which a thinker addresses himself. He thus links the sociology of

knowledge with research on publics and audiences that was pioneered by the Chicago school

of sociology' (for example, see Park 1904). Znaniecki shows that thinkers - at least in

differentiated societies - are not likely to address their total society but rather only selected

segments or publics. The thinker is related to a social circle: and this circle expects him to live

up to certain of its demands, in exchange for which it grants him recognition and support.

9

Page 10: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

Men of knowledge anticipate the demands of their public; and they tend to form self-images,

select data, and seize upon problems in terms of their actual or anticipated audiences. Men of

knowledge may thus be classified in regard to their social roles and their publics. Hence it

becomes possible to understand the emergence of such special roles as that of sage,

technologist, and scholar in terms of the differentiated publics to which they address

themselves. [See INTELLECTUALS.]

It is impossible to discuss or even enumerate within the confines of this article the recent

American studies which either directly or indirectly contribute to the further development of

the sociology of knowledge. This state of affairs may itself be an indicator of the continued

strength of this research orientation. A few references will have to suffice.

Research in the field of social role, the sociology of science, the professions and

occupations, and the sociology of communications and public opinion has already been

mentioned. In other areas can be listed the studies exploring the relations between minority

status and originality of intellectual perspective, to which Veblen (1919) made significant

contributions, and of which the recent work by Melvin Seeman (1956) seems an excellent

example; the studies in the history of sociological or philosophical theories, in which

conceptualizations derived from the sociology of knowledge have been utilized - for example,

the works of C. Wright Mills on pragmatism (1964); the studies that relate thought styles of

American academic men to the structure and functioning of the American academy - such as

Logan Wilson's Academic Man (1942), Lazarsfeld and Thielens' Academic Mind (1958), an

analysis of social scientists' reactions to the threats posed by the McCarthy era, and Caplow

and McGee's Academic Marketplace (1958); general studies of the settings and contexts in

which intellectuals play their peculiar roles, such as Lewis Coser's Men of Ideas (1965); and

Fritz Machlup's large-scale study, The Production and Distribution of Knowledge in the

United States (1962). More detailed studies - such as Peter Berger's recent attempt to account

for the popularity of psychoanalysis in America (1965) and John Bennett's study of divergent

interpretations of the same culture by different social scientists in terms of their divergent

backgrounds and social perspectives (1946)—have also been very much in evidence in recent

years.

The sociology of knowledge was marked in its early history by a tendency to set up

grandiose hypothetical schemes. These contributed a number of extremely suggestive leads.

Recently its practitioners have tended to withdraw from such ambitious undertakings and to

restrict themselves to somewhat more manageable investigations. Although this tendency has

been an antidote to earlier types of premature generalizations, it also carries with it the danger

10

Page 11: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

of trivialization. Perhaps the sociology of knowledge of the future will return to the more

daring concerns of its founders, thus building upon the accumulation of careful and detailed

investigations by preceding generations of researchers.

[Directly related are the entries MARXIST SOCIOLOGY; SOCIAL STRUCTURE, article on SOCIAL

STRUCTURAL ANALYSIS. Other relevant material may be found in LITERATURE, article on THE

SOCIOLOGY OF LITERATURE; SCIENCE; and in the biographies of BACON; DEWEY; DURKHEIM;

HALBWACIIS; JAMES; MANNHEIM; MARX; PEIRCE; SCHELER; SOROKIN; VEBLEN; WEBER, MAX;

ZNANIECKI.]

BIBLIOGRAPHY

For extensive bibliographies on the sociology of knowledge, see Merton 1949; Mannheim

1929-1931; Maquet 1949; and Wolff 1959.

BACON, FRANCIS (1605) 1958 The Advancement of Learning. Edited with an introduction by G.

W. Kitchin. London: Dent; New York: Dutton.

BARBER, BERNARD 1952 Science and the Social Order. Glencoe, 111.: Free Press.

BENNETT, JOHN W. (1946) 1956 The Interpretation of Pueblo Culture: A Question of Values.

Pages 203-216 in Douglas G. Haring (editor), Personal Character and Cultural Milieu: A

Collection of Readings. 3d ed., rev. Syracuse Univ. Press - First published in Volume 2 of the

Southwestern Journal of Anthropology.

BERGER, PETER L. 1965 Toward a Sociological Understanding of Psychoanalysis. Social

Research 32:26-41.

CAPLOW, THEODORE 1954 The Sociology of Work. Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press.

CAPLOW, THEODORE; and McGEE, REECE J. 1958 The Academic Marketplace. New York: Basic

BooJcs. - A paperback edition was published in 1961 by Wiley.

CORNFORD. FRANCIS M. 1912 From Religion to Philosophy: A Study in the Origins of Western

Speculations. New York: Longmans. - A paperback edition was published in 1957 by Harper.

COSER. LEWIS A. 1965 Men of Ideas: A Sociologist's View. New York: Free Press.

DAHLKE, H. OTTO 1940 The Sociology of Knowledge. Pages 64-89 in Harry E. Barnes, Howard

Becker, and Frances B. Becker (editors), Contemporary Social Theory. New York: Appieton

DtGRE. GERALD L. 1943 Society and Ideoiogit: An Inquiry Into the Sociology of Knowledge.

New York: Columbia Univ. Press.

DURKHEIM, EMILE (1912) 1954 The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life. London: Allen &

Unwin; New York: Macmillan. - First published as Les formes elementaires de la vie

religieuse, le systeme totemique en Australie. A paperback edition was published in 1961 by

11

Page 12: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

Collier.

DURKHEIM, EMILE: and MAUSS, MARCEL (1903) 1963 Primitive Classification. Translated and

edited by Rodney Needham. Univ. of Chicago Press. - First published as "De quelques formes

primitives de classification" in L'annee sociologique.

GRANET, MARCEL (1934) 1950 Le pensee chinoise. Paris: Michel.

HALBWACHS, MAURICE 1925 Les cadres sociaux de la memoire. Paris: Alcan.

HALL, OSWALD 1948 Stages of a Medical Career. American Journal of Sociology 53:327-336.

HARRISON, JANE ELLEN (1912) 1927 Themis.- A Study of the Social Origins of Greek Religion.

2d ed. rev. Cambridge Univ. Press.

HUGHES, EVERETT C. 1958 Men and Their Work. Glencoe, 111.: Free Press.

LAZARSFELD, PAUL F.; and THIELENS, WAGNER JR. 1958 The Academic Mind: Social Scientists in

a Time of Crisis. A report of the Bureau of Applied Social Research, Columbia University.

Glencoe, III.: Free Press.

LEVI-STRAUSS, CLAUDE 1945 French Sociology. Pages 503-537 in Georges Gurvitch and Wilbert

E. Moore (editors), Twentieth Century Sociology. New York Philosophical Library.

MACHLUP, FRITZ 1962 The Production and Distribution of Knowledge in the United States.

Princeton Univ. Press.

MANNHEIM, KARL (1922-1940)1953 Essays on Sociology and Social Psychology. Edited by Paul

Kecskemeti London: Routledge. - See especially pages 77-164 in "Conservative Thought.

MANNHEIM, KARL (1923-1929) 1952 Essays on the Sociology of Knowledge. Edited by Paul

Kecskemeti. New York: Oxford Univ. Press. -* See especially pages 191-229 on

"Competition as a Cultural Phenomenon"

MANNHEIM, KARL (1929-1931) 1954 Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of

Knowledge. New York: Harcourt; London: Routledge. - First published in German. A

paperback edition was published in 1955 by Harcourt.

MAQUET, JACQUES J. (1949) 1951 The Sociology Of Knowledge, Its Structure and Its Relation to

the Philosophy of Knowledge: A Critical Analysis of the Systems of Karl Mannheim and

Pitirim A. Sorokin. Translated by John F. Locke. Boston: Beacon. - First published in French.

MARSHALL, T. H. (1934-1949) 1950 Citizenship and SocraZ Class, and Other Essays.

Cambridge Univ. Press.

MARX. KARL (1859) 1913 A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. Chicago: Kerr. -

First published as Zur Kritik der politischen Okonomie.

MARX. KARL; and ENGELS, FRIEDRICH (1845-1846) 1939 The German Ideology. Parts 1 and 3.

With an introduction by R. Pascal. New York: International Publishers. — Written in 1845-

12

Page 13: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

1846, the full text was first published in 1932 as Die deutsche Ideologic and republished by

Dietz Verlag in 1953.

MARX, KARL: and ENGZLS. FRIEDRICH (1848) 1963 The Communist Manifesto. New York:

Russell. - A paperback edition was published in 1964 by Washington Square Press.

MEAD, GEORGE H. 1934 Mind, Self and Society From the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist.

Edited by Charles W. Morris. Univ. of Chicago Press. - Published posthumously

MERTON, ROBERT K. (1949) 1957 Social Theory and Social Structure. Rev. & enl. ed. Glencoe,

III.: Free Press. - See especially Part 3 on 'The Sociology of Knowledge" and Part 4 on "The

Sociology of Science."

MILLS. C. WRIGHT 1963 Power, Politics and People: The Collected Essays of C. Wright Mills.

Edited and introduced by Irving Louis Horowitz. New York: Oxford Univ. Press. - See

especially pages. 423-438 on "Language, Logic and Culture," pages 439-452 on "Situated

Actions and Vocabularies of Motive," and pages 453-456 on "Methodological Consequences

of the Sociology of Knowledge."

MILLS, C. WRIGHT 1964 Sociology and Pragmatism: The Higher Learning in America. Edited

with an introduction by Irving Louis Horowitz. New York: Paine-Whitman. - A revision of

Mills's unpublished doctoral dissertation.

PARK. ROBERT E. 1904 Masse und Publikum: Eine methodologische und soziologische

Untersuchung. Bern: Lack & Grunau.

PARSONS, TALCOTT (1938-1953) 1963 Essays in Sociological Theory. Rev. ed. Glencoe,

III.: Free Press. RANULF, SVEND (1938) 1964 MoraJ Indignation and Middle Class

Psychology: A Sociological Study. New York: Schocken. - The appendix contains a well-

documented attack on Scheler's theory of resentment.

SCHELER, MAX (1926) 1960 Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft. 2d ed., rev. Bern: Francke.

SEEMAN, MELVIN 1956 Intellectual Perspective and Adjustment to Minority Group Status. Social

Problems 3:142-153.

SOROKIN, PITIRIM A. 1928 Contemporary Sociological Theories. New York: Harper. --> A

paperback edition was published in 1964 by Harper as Contemporary Sociological Theories

Through the First Quarter of the Twentieth Century.

SOROKIN, PITIRIM A. (1937-1941) 1962 Social and Cultural Dynamics. 4 vols. Englewood

Cliffs. N.J.: Bed-minster Press. - Volume 1: Fluctuation of Forms of Art. Volume 2:

Fluctuation of Systems of Truth, Ethics, and Law. Volume 3: Fluctuation of Social Re-

lationships, War, and Revolution. Volume 4: Basic Problems, Principles, and Methods.

SOROKIN, PITIRIM A. (1943) 1964 Sociocultural Causality, Space, Time: A Study of Referential

13

Page 14: Sociology of Knowledge - Coser

Principles of Sociology and Social Science. New York: Russell.

SPEIER, HANS (1938) 1952 The Social Determination of Ideas. Pages 95-111 in Hans Speier.

Social Order and the Risks of War: Papers in Political Sociology. New York: Stewart.

STARK, WERNER 1958 The Sociology of Knowledge: An Essay in Aid of a Deeper Understanding

of the History of Ideas. London: Routledge; Glencoe. III.: Free Press.

VEBLEN, THORSTEIN (1891-1913) 1961 The Place of Science in Modern Civilisation, and Other

Essays. New York: Russell.

VEBLEN, THORSTEIN (1918)1957 The Higher Learning in America: A Memorandum on the

Conduct of Universities by Business Men. New York: Sagamore.

VEBLEN, THORSTEIN (1919) 1948 The Intellectual Preeminence of Jews in Modern Europe.

Pages 467-479 in Thorstein Veblen, The Portable Vtblen. Edited with an introduction by Max

Lerner. New York: Viking.

WILSON, LOGAN (1942) 1964 The Academic Man: A Study in the Sociology of a Profession. New

York: Octagon.

WOLFF, KURT H. 1959 The Sociology of Knowledge and Sociological Theory. Pages 567-602 in

Llewellyn Gross (editor), Symposium on Sociological Theory New York: Harper.

ZNANIECKI, FLORIAN 1940 The Social Role of the Man of Knowledge. New York: Columbia

Univ. Press.

14