some principles in the art of naming

Upload: bart-mazzetti

Post on 03-Apr-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    1/24

    SOME PRINCIPLES IN THE ART OF NAMING

    (c) 2013 Bart A. Mazzetti

    1

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    2/24

    1. The difference between the name and the symbol.

    Michael A. Augros, Democritus and the Problem of Number, p. 7.

    That a name signifies what is one per se is what distinguishes it from another kind ofartificial sign, the symbol. Symbol is also used as a generic word for the two species

    name and symbol, but when symbol is used to mean the species of artificial sign

    distinguished from name, it differs from it as signifying things without any attention towhether or not they are one per se. As Charles De Koninck notes on page 10 of TheHollow Universe, St. Thomas, in speaking of symbols of faith which are collections of

    propositions of the faith gathered not according to intrinsic order, but according to

    circumstantial needs of the time, says symbolum importat quamdam collectionem. Theword symbol itself comes from the Greek for thrown together. Hence a symbol differs

    from a name in that a name is an artificial sign given to things as a result of their being

    grasped as somehow one per se, whereas a symbol is an artificial sign given to thingswithout their being so grasped. Hence it is possible to give a symbol to a heap or list or

    jumble or random pile of things which have no per se unity at all, whereas it is impossible

    to give a proper name to such a mess. It is also possible, of course, to give a symbol tosomething which is one per se, e.g. Let this circle be called A, but A is only a symbol

    so long as it is used to designate the thing without any attendance to the per se unity it has.

    Michael A. Augros, ibid., p. 7.

    ...[S]ince science is of the necessary, and what is one by accident (e.g. what is one by

    being said of or by belonging to one thing, or by being in one place, or in general what isone not through itself but through happening to be with the unity of some other thing) is

    not one of necessity, ...so neither can there be a science of it, or a definition, or even a

    name. For example, although rational animal is composed of two names, the one thingnamed by these is, as such, a single thing, since something undetermined in animal is

    further determined by rational. Hence, man, as such, has unity in and of itself. One of

    the terms in mans definition is perfective of the other and they are found together of

    necessity; it is impossible to find a complete rational nature which is not also an animal,since to be rational is to be a certain kind of animal, it is a determinate way of being an

    animal. Therefore man is not a mere symbol, but a name, and the thing so named admits

    of a real definition (according to genus and differences, or according to causes), and therecan be science about that thing. But the case is different with something like opinionated,

    fashionable, overpaid, nazi. No two of the things just mentioned belong together of

    necessity, although all four of them may happen to belong to some one person, Hilary.There is no necessary union between opinionated and fashionable; these can be found

    separately, and being opinionated is not a determinate way of being fashionable any

    more than fashionable determines a way of being opinionated. They are not foundtogether by reason of anything in themselves, although they might happen to be together in

    some third thing, such as Hilary.

    Michael A. Augros, Spring 1993 Scrapbook (Scrapboo. 1), The Art of Naming, n. 6.

    A name is an artificial sign of a thing which is one of itself, whereas a symbol is an

    artificial sign of things which are one through something other than themselves. In theMetaphysics, Aristotle says things like white, vagrant, thrice-married plumber are one

    2

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    3/24

    through something other than themselves, in this case the man to whom all these things

    happen to belong. Any sign for such a collection or heap of things which are one becausethey are all in one subject, or all in one place, or all on one list in somebodys mind, is a

    symbol (as distinguished from a name). What, then, of signs we all would call names, such

    as musician and negro? A musician is a musical man, and a negro is a black man. Thesehave no more unity of their own, it seems, than white man. But musician does not

    differ logically from musical, which really names music, as in the art (in the genus of

    habit, and ultimately of quality), though the ending is changed, since music names thequality in the mode of a substance, in the mode of something absolute, so that it must berenamed musical to be predicable of a substance. One cannot say Socrates is music,

    but Socrates is musical or Socrates is a musician which do not differ logically from

    Socrates has the art of music. Likewise with negro, which names a racial quality thatcan be found only in man, and which is an inseparable accident from any in whom it is

    found.

    2. On proportional naming.

    Michael Augros,Philosophical and Theological Scrapbook #6. Fall 1994 (Scrapboo 6),

    Logic, nn. 13-14.

    13) n 879 In V Metaphysicorum Lectio VIII, St. Thomas distinguishes 2 sorts of

    proportional naming:

    Proportione vero vel analogia sunt unum quaecumque in hoc conveniunt, quod hoc

    se habet ad illud sicut aliud ad aliud. Et hoc quidem potest accipi duobus modis, vel in eoquod aliqua duo habent diversas habitudines ad unum; sicut sanativum de urina dictum

    habitudinem significat signi sanitatis; de medicina vero, quia significat habitudinem causae

    respectu eiusdem. Vel in eo quod est eadem proportio duorum ad diversa, sicuttranquillitatis ad mare et serenitatis ad aerem. Tranquillitas enim est quies maris et

    serenitas aeris

    And at nn 535 (Book IV, Lectio 1), he says:

    Dicit ergo primo, quod ens sive quod est, dicitur multipliciter. Sed sciendum quod

    aliquid praedicatur de diversis multipliciter: quandoque quidem secundum rationemomnino eamdem, et tunc dicitur de eis univoce praedicari, sicut animal de equo et bove.

    --Quandoque vero secundum rationes omnino diversas; et tunc dicitur de eis aequivoce

    praedicari, sicut canis de sidere et animali. --Quandoquae vero secundum rationes quaepartim sunt diversae et partim non diversae: diversae quidem secundum quod diversas

    habitudines important, unae autem secundum quod ad unum aliquid et idem istae diversae

    habitudines referentur; et illud dicitur analogice praedicari, idest proportionaliter, proutunumquodque secundum suam habitudinem ad illud unum refertur.

    And in Summa Contra Gentiles (I.33), he says:

    Ubi est pura aequivocatio, nulla similitudo in rebus attenditur, sed solum unitas

    nominis ... quando unum de pluribus secundum puram aequivocationem praedicatur, ex

    uno eorum non possumus duci in cognitionem alterius: name cognitio rerum non dependetex vocibus, sed ex nominum ratione.

    3

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    4/24

    And in Summa Contra Gentiles (I.34), he says:

    Relinquitur quod ea quae de Deo et rebus aliis dicuntur, praedicantur neque

    univoce neque aequivoce, sed analogice: hoc est, secundum ordinem vel respectum ad

    aliquid unum.

    Quod quidem dupliciter contingit. Uno modo, secundum quod multa habent

    respectum ad aliquid unum: sicut secundum respectum ad unam sanitatem animal dicitur

    sanum ut eius subiectum medicina ut eius effectivum, cibus ut conservativum, urina utsigna.

    Alio modo, secundum quod duorum attenditur ordo vel respectus, non ad aliquidalterum, sed ad unum ipsorum: sicut ens de substantia et accidente dicitur secundum quod

    accidens ad substantiam respectum habet, non quod substantia et accidnens ad aliquid

    tertium referantur.

    Huiusmodi igitur nomina de Deo et rebus aliis non dicuntur analogice secundum

    primum modum, oporteret enim aliquid Deo ponere prius: sed modo secundo.

    In huiusmodi autem analogica praedicatione ordo attenditur idem secundum nomenet secundum rem quandoque, quandoque vero non idem. Nam ordo nominis sequiturordinem cognitionis: quia est signum intelligibilis conceptionis. Quando igitur id quod est

    prius secundum rem, invenitur etiam cognitione prius idem invenitur prius secundum

    nominis rationem et secundum rei naturam: sicut substantia est prior accidente et natura,

    inquantum substantia est causa accidentis; et cognitione, inquantum substantia indefinitione accidentis ponitur. Et ideo ens dicitur prius de substantia quam de accidente et

    secundum nominis rationem [et secundum naturam]. --Quando vero id quod est prius

    secundum naturam, est posterius secundum cognitionem, tunc in analogicis non est idemordo secundum rem et secundum nominis rationem. Sicut virtus sanandi quae est in

    sanativus, prior est naturaliter sanitate quae est in animali, sicut causa effectu; sed quia

    hanc virtutem per effectum cognoscimus, ideo etiam ex effectu nominamus. Et inde estsanativum est prius ordine rei, sed animal dicitur per prius sanum secundum nominis

    rationem.

    Sic igitur, quia ex rebus aliis in Dei cognitionem pervenimus, res nominum de Deoet rebus aliis dictorum per prius est in Deo secundum suum modum sed ratio nominis per

    posterius. Unde et nominari dicitur a suis causatis.

    Naming things proportionally is one way of naming them equivocally for a reason. There

    are others, such as the retaining of a common name for all the species other than one which

    gets a new name because of something significant about it. E.g. animal is divided into

    man and the animals, so animal can mean two things; according to one of which it issaid of man, and according to the other of which it is not. Likewise when finger is

    divided into thumb and the other four fingers. Again, undergoing has threemeanings, each shedding a part found in the previous definition. These are ways of naming

    things equivocally for a reason, but not so much ways of naming things proportionally.

    In order for the naming of things equivocally for a reason to be proportional

    naming, there must be some sort of proportion, or, at least, a ratio which is the basis of the

    naming.

    4

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    5/24

    (Proportion even in English first means a ratio of one quantity to another, and

    later a likeness of such ratios. But, following Euclid, it is best to use proportion to meana likeness of ratios, and ratio for a simple ratio of one thing to another.)

    IF WE COMPARE TWO THINGS TO EACH OTHER

    1)- And we name them the same because of ratio they have to each other, then they are

    named Proportionally. E.g. Substance and accident are called being equivocallyfor a reason, namely the ratio that accident has to substance.

    2)- And we name them the same, but not because of a ratio they have to each other, then

    they are named equivocally by chance. E.g. piece of baseball equipment and nocturnalwinged animal are called bat equivocally by chance, since they are not so named

    because of any relation between the two.

    IF WE COMPARE TWO THINGS TO OTHER THINGS

    3)- And they have the same ratio to different things, then they are named Proportionally.E.g. a certain kind of statement is to the subject it helps us conclude about as the innermost

    boundary is to the thing contained in it, and hence the statement is called a Place after

    the innermost boundary of the containing body.

    4)- And they have different ratios to the same thing, then they are named Proportionally.

    E.g. a scalpel has one relation to the art of medicine, namely it is an instrument of it, and a

    doctor has another relation to the art of medicine, namely he is the subject of it. Hence boththe scalpel and the doctor are called medical.

    5)- And they have the same ratio to the same thing, then they are named univocally. E.g. ifa scalpel and a bandage both have the same relation to the art of medicine, namely that

    they are instruments of it, and if that is why each is called medical, then they are called

    medical univocally.

    6)- And they have different ratios to different things, then they are named equivocally by

    chance. E.g. if the wooden baseball equipment has one relation to the sport of baseball, and

    the nocturnal winged animal has another relation to its cave, this cannot be a reason fornaming both the equipment and the animal bat.

    1) 2 things have ratio to each other = PROPORTIONAL NAMING

    2) 2 things have no ratio = PURELY EQUIVOCAL NAMING

    3) 2 things have same ratio to different things = PROPORTIONAL NAMING

    4) 2 things have different ratios to same thing = PROPORTIONAL NAMING

    5) 2 things have same ratio to same thing = UNIVOCAL NAMING

    6) 2 things have different ratios to different things = PURELY EQUIVOCAL NAMING

    5

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    6/24

    14) Equivocally = named unequally, univocally = named equally (ex aequo),

    analogously = named proportionally.

    Cf. Michael Augros,Notes from the Berquist Seminars (Duane.4), n. 644:

    664) ANALOGY OF NAMES. A name may be equivocal either by chance or for a reason.

    But name used equivocally for a reason is broader than name used proportionally.

    Sometimes St. Thomas limits divisio to the separation of parts of some whole,either composed or universal, and other times he is willing to use it to mean any kind of

    separation, e.g. of a word into its meanings or in a negative statement. Likewise, St.

    Thomas will sometimes call being a genus. In a similar way, we might say that any nameused equivocally for a reason is used proportionally in some very loose way of speaking,

    but more strictly we should say that we have a proportional name only if there is actually

    a proportion in Euclids sense, or at least a ratio.

    When Dr. Berquist tried to pin down Dionne about the sorts of name used

    equivocally for a reason, Dionne seemed unwilling to call all of them analogous orproportional names. E.g. when isosceles is divided into isosceles and equilateral, or

    animal into animal and man, or finger into finger and thumb, and disposition into

    disposition and habit, or episteme into episteme and sophia, or man into man and

    boy, or cat into cat and kitten, Dionne said these are not examples of proportionalnaming. When we say Socrates is an animal, and then we deny that he is an animal (in the

    sense of animal that is opposed to man), there are two meanings of the word animal

    here, and it is not by chance. At first, it seems that one is distinguishing between the genusand the species, as if distinguishing dog from animal, which is odd. But really there are

    two meanings attached to the common name. Consider the example with animal. One

    meaning is sensitive living thing, which is said of Socrates, the other is irrationalsensitive living thing which is not said of Socrates. It is unhelpful to describe this kind of

    name used equivocally for a reason as a proportional name. There is no proportion.

    Rather, it seems better to say that one species keeps the common name, and the other gets a

    new name because of something significant about it. Or, as in the last two examples, whathas the common notion fully keeps that name, as a grown cat keeps the common name

    cat, whereas the kitten, as distinguished from the adult cat, gets a new name because it is

    imperfect.

    Again, undergoing seems to have three meanings. First, it means receiving and

    going from contrary to contrary and receiving the worse of the two, then it meansreceiving and going from contrary to contrary, and finally it means receiving. We lose

    a part of the previous definition each time. This does not seem to be a proportional name,

    but a name having three different meanings, each one of which sheds a part of the previousone.

    Again, seeing is said of the eye, the imagination, and reason not so much by a

    proportion or by shedding parts of a definition as you go along, but by the likenessbetween their acts.

    As for proportional names ... we can either compare two things to each other, or thetwo things to other things. We then have these possibilities:

    6

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    7/24

    1) The 2 things have a ratio to each other

    2) The 2 things do not have a ratio

    3) The 2 things have the same ratio to different things

    4) The 2 things have different ratios to the same thing

    5) The 2 things have the same ratio to the same thing

    6) The 2 things have different ratios to different things

    Now, in 6), if we say health has a certain relation to the body, and father has a different

    relation to son, there is no reason in any of this to name any of the things by the same

    name. Hence, if any 2 things (such as health and a father) are named the same, having onlydifferent ratios to different things, they are named equivocally by chance.

    Now in 5), if we say a scalpel has a relation to the art of medicine, namely that ofan instrument, and a bandage has this same relation to the art of medicine, and if they are

    both named medical in virtue of this same relation the have to the same thing, then they

    are so called purely univocally.

    Now in 4), if we say a scalpel has a relation to the art of medicine, namely that of

    an instrument, and a doctor has a different relation to the art of medicine, namely as its

    subject, then if they are both named medical in virtue of these different relations to thesame thing, then they are so called PROPORTIONALLY (for it is not univocal, being

    named the same for different reasons, but it is not purely equivocal, each having that name

    for not entirely unrelated reasons).

    Now in 3), if we say a certain kind of statement has a relation to the subject it helps

    us conclude about, and the innermost boundary of the containing body has the same

    relation to the contained body, then if they are both named place in virtue of these samerelations they have to different things, then they are so called PROPORTIONALLY.

    Now in 2), if we are simply comparing two things having the same name, and theyhave no relation to one another in virtue of which they are named the same, e.g. the

    baseball bat and the vampire bat, or the bark of a tree and the bark of a dog, then they are

    named purely equivocally.

    And in 1), if we are simply comparing two things having the same name, and they

    do have a relation to one another in virtue of which they are named the same, e.g.substance and accident are both called being because of a relation of accident to

    substance (which is called being first, or before accident), then they are named

    PROPORTIONALLY.

    Hence, we say being of substance and quantity because one is called being

    first, and the other is called being because it is something of a being in the first sense.

    Here we have the same name given to different things because of a ratio of one to theother. But if we said being only of quantity and quality, then it would be because they

    7

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    8/24

    have different ratios to the same thing, namely substance. But since being is in fact said

    of all three, we have both kinds of proportional naming involved.

    In summary, analogous or proportional names are names said of two things for a

    reason, namely by reason of

    1) A ratio of one to the other, as being is said of substance and quantity

    2) The same ratio they have to other things (a strict proportion)

    3) The different ratios they have to the same thing, as being is said of quantity

    and quality.

    All three of these can be found in St. Thomas, namely in the commentary on the

    chapter on one in the Metaphysics, and in the Summa Contra Gentiles (the chapter onhow God is named analogously with creatures). One must put these two texts together to

    get all three.

    It is not helpful to call the example of undergoing an example of proportional

    naming, but it is equivocal for a reason.

    2 is said of 2 and 3, and because 2 is just 2 it keeps the old name, but because 3 is 2+ 1, it gets a new name it is not just a 2. You dont call it 2 because that is an insult to 3.

    This kind of naming should not be called proportional naming, either. It is keeping the

    common name for the species which does not have anything significant added.

    8

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    9/24

    3. The primary division of names.

    Michael Augros, Spring 1993 Scrapbook (Scrapboo.1), The Art of Naming, n. 3,

    revised: Original version and my alternate division.1

    (Original Version)

    3) It is in this part of logic, the art of naming,

    that we distinguish the name from the symbol,

    and then the proper name from the figurative or

    improper name.

    Among the proper names, we distinguish theuniversal from the individual name.

    Among the universal names, we distinguish theequivocal use of a word from the univocal use

    of a word, and we define the denominative use

    of a word.

    Among universal names (to the extent that they

    are used univocally), we distinguish the five

    kinds of name: the genus, the species, the

    difference, the property, and the accident.

    Among universal names (to the extent that theyare used equivocally), we distinguish the mere-

    ly accidentally equivocal use of names from the

    intended equivocal use of names.

    And we distinguish the intended equivocal use

    of names, or the analogous use of names, from

    the metaphor.

    And among the analogous uses of names, we

    distinguish several different ways of so using

    names, e.g. based on a proportion, or a relation

    to one, or a likeness, or by descent from one(see Boethius commentary on the Categories).

    (Alternate division by B.A.M.)

    In this part of logic, the art of naming, we dis-

    tinguish the name from the symbol,

    and then the universal or common name from

    the individual or private name.

    Among the universal names, we distinguish the

    proper from the improper or figurative name.

    Among the proper names,

    we distinguish the equivocal or unequal use ofa word from the univocal or equal use of a

    word, and we define the denominative use of a

    word.

    Among universal names (to the extent that they

    are used univocally), we distinguish the five

    kinds of name: the genus or general name, the

    species or specific name, the difference or dis-

    tinguishing name, the property, and the acci-

    dent.

    Among universal names (to the extent that theyare used equivocally), we distinguish the mere-

    ly accidentally equivocal use of names from the

    intended equivocal use of names.

    And we distinguish the intended equivocal use

    of names from the metaphor.

    And among the equivocal uses of names we

    distinguish the proportional or analogous uses

    of names from those that are not so used.

    1 As the reader will observe, my presentation supposes that names are immediately divided into the common

    oruniversal(= the appellative) (e.g. man, ox) and theprivate orindividual(e.g. Socrates, Plato), then,

    that the common is subdivided into theproperand the improperorfigurative (e.g. lion said of the beast and

    of Winston Churchill). I also present an expanded division of the equivocal use of names in the light of the

    preceding section.

    9

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    10/24

    Again, in this part of logic, we not only dis-

    tinguish the meanings of words, but we also

    distinguish the meaning of a word from its

    etymology (Bertrand Russell and Hobbes fail

    to do this all over the place): see Charles DeKoninck, Abstraction from Matter, 150-152.

    And among the proportional uses of names, we

    distinguish several different ways of so using

    names, e.g. when two things compared to each

    other have a ratio to each other; or have the

    same ratio to different things; or have different

    ratios to the same thing.

    Among the uses of names that are equivocal

    but not proportional, we distinguish those useswhere one species keeps the common name,

    but the other or others do not; where onespecies keeps the common definition, but the

    others shed part of it; where one thing is like

    another thing; and where many things descend

    from one.

    Again, in this part of logic, we not only dis-

    tinguish the meanings of words, but we also

    distinguish the meaning of a word from its

    etymology (Bertrand Russell and Hobbes fail

    to do this all over the place): see Charles DeKoninck, Abstraction from Matter, 150-152.

    4. The division of names in sum.

    Name

    Symbol

    Name

    Name

    Individual (Private)Universal (Common) (= the appellative)

    Improper (Figurative)

    Proper

    Denominative

    Univocal (Equal)Equivocal (Unequal)

    By chanceFor a reason

    Proportional

    Two things compared to each other have a ratio to each other

    Two things compared to other things

    10

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    11/24

    Have the same ratio to different things

    Have different ratios to the same thing

    Not proportional

    One species keeps the common name, the other or others do not

    One species keeps the common definition, the others shed part of it

    One thing is like another thingSeveral things descend from one thing

    11

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    12/24

    5. On the difference between that from which and that with respect to which a

    name has been imposed in order to signify.

    St. Thomas Aquinas, Qu. Disp. de Ver. q. 14, art. 1, obj. 8, ad 8 (tr. B.A.M.).

    obj. 8. Further, each name chiefly signifies that from which [id a quo] it is im-

    posed. But the name verbum is imposed either from verberatione aeris, or from boatu,

    which word is nothing other than verum boans. This, then, is chiefly signified by the nameofverbum. But this belongs to God in no way except metaphorically. Verbum, or word,then, is not properly said in the divine.

    ad 8 To the eighth it must be said that a name is said to be imposed from something

    [ab aliquod] in two ways: either on the part of the one who imposes the name, or on the

    part of the thing upon which it is imposed.Now on the part of the thing a name is said to be imposed from that [ab illo] by

    which the account of the thing which the name signifies is completedand this is the

    specific difference of that thing. And this is what is principally signified by the name.

    But because essential differences are unknown to us, we sometimes use accidentsor effects in their place, as is said in the eighth book of theMetaphysics; and we name the

    thing according to this. And so that which is taken in place of essential differences is that

    from which [id a quo] the name is imposed on the part of the one who imposes [the name],just as lapis, stone, is imposed from an effect, which is laedere pedem, to hurt the foot.

    And this should not be principally signified by the name, but that in place of which this is

    put.

    N.B.That is, what should be principally signified by the vocal sound verbum is the ratio of

    the thing, and not that which is put in place of such a ratio, which is the vocal sound taken

    from verberatio, etc.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol. Ia, q. 13, art. 8 (tr. B.A.M.).

    To the eighth one proceeds as follows.

    obj. 1. It seems that the name God is not the name of a nature. For Damascenesays in the first book [sc. De Fide] that God is said from theein, which is to run, and to

    cherish all things; or from aethein, that is, to burn (for our God is a fire consuming all

    malice); or from theasthai, which is to consider all things. But all these things pertain tooperation. Therefore, the name God signifies an operation, and not a nature.

    obj. 2. Further, to the extent that something is named by us, to that extent it is

    known. But the divine nature is unknown to us. Therefore, the name God does not signify

    the divine nature.

    s.c. But to the contrary is what Ambrose says in the first bookDe Fide, that God isthe name of a nature.

    corp. I reply that it must be said that that from which [id a quo] a name is imposedin order to signify is not always the same as that with respect to which [id ad quod] the

    name is imposed in order to signify. For just as we know a thing from its properties or

    12

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    13/24

    operations, so at times we name the substance of a thing from some operation or property

    or it, just as we name the substance of a stone from some action of it because laedit pedem,it hurts the foot. Still the name has not been imposed in order to signify this action, but

    the substance of the stone. But if there are things which are known to us according to

    themselves [secundum se], like heat, cold, whiteness, and the like, they are not named fromother things. And so in such things what the name signifies and that from which it is

    imposed in order to signify are the same thing. Therefore, since God is not known to us in

    His own nature, but he is made known to us from His operations or effects, we are able toname Him from these things, as was said above. And so the nameDeus, God, is the nameof an operation, with respect to that from which it is imposed in order to signify. For the

    name is imposed from the universal providence of things; for all men speaking about God

    intend this to name God, because he has a universal providence over all things. And soDionysius says in chapter 12 ofAbout the Divine Names that the Deity is that which

    watches over all things with perfect providence and goodness. But the nameDeus, God,

    taken from this operation has been imposed in order to signify the divine nature.

    ad 1. To the first, then, it must be said that all the things set down by Damascene

    pertain to providence, from which the name God is imposed in order to signify.

    ad 2. To the second its must be said that according as we can know the nature of

    any thing from its properties and effects, so we can signify it by a name. And so because

    we can know the substance of a stone from its property according to itself [secundum se],by knowing what a stone is, the name stone signifies the very nature of a stone as it is in

    itself, for it signifies the definition of a stone, by virtue of which we know what a stone is.

    For the ratio which the name signifies is the definition, as is said in the fourth book of theMetaphysics. But from the divine effects we cannot know the divine nature as it is in itself

    such that we know about it what it is, but by way of eminence and causality and negation,

    as was said above. And thus the name Deus, God, signifies the divine nature. For thename has been imposed in order to signify something existing above all things, which is

    the principle of all things, and is removed from all things. For those naming God intend to

    signify this.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., Ia, q. 18, art. 2. c. (tr. B.A.M.).

    I reply that it must be said that, as is clear from the things stated (q. 17, art. 3), ourintellect, which is properly equipped to know the whatness of a thing as its proper object,

    takes [knowledge] from sense, the proper objects of which are external accidents. And this

    is why we arrive at knowing the essence of a thing from the things which appear about itoutwardly [ex his quae exterius apparent de re]. And because we name a thing as we know

    it, as is clear from the things said above (q. 13, art. 1), it is for this reason that names for

    the most part are imposed from exterior properties in order to signify the essences ofthings. And so names of this sort sometimes are taken properly for the very essences of the

    things upon which they are principally imposed for the purpose of signifying. But

    sometimes they are taken for the properties from which they are imposed, and this is done

    less properly. For example, it is clear that the name body has been imposed in order tosignify a certain genus of substances by reason of the fact that three dimensions are found

    in them, and as a result sometimes the name body is put down in order to signify three

    dimensions, according as body is put down for a species of quantity.

    13

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    14/24

    The same must be said of life [vita]. For the name life is taken from something

    appearing outside a thing [ex quodam exterius apparenti circa rem], which is to moveitself, yet it has not been imposed in order to signify this, but in order to signify the

    substance to which it belongs to move itself according to its own nature, or to apply itself

    in any way to an activity. And according to this, living [vivere] is nothing other thanexisting in such a nature, and life signifies this very thing, but abstractly, just as the name

    (a) run [cursus] signifies running [or to run, currere] itself abstractly. And so [a]

    living [thing] [vivum] is not an accidental predicate, but a substantial one. But sometimeslife is taken less properly for the activities of life, from which the name life is taken, asthe Philosopher say in the ninth book of the Ethics, that living is principally sensing or

    understanding.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., Ia, q. 13, art. 2, ad 3 (tr. B.A.M.).

    To the second it must be said that in the signification of names, sometimes thatfrom which [id a quo] a name is imposed in order to signify is one thing, and that with

    respect to which [id ad quod] the name is imposed in order to signify is something else,

    just as the name lapis, or stone, is imposed from the fact that laedit pedem, it hurts thefoot; yet it is not imposed in order to signify what hurts the foot, but in order to signify a

    certain species of body; otherwise everything that hurts the foot would be a stone.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,In I Sent., dist. 23, q. 1, art. 2, ad 1 (tr. B.A.M.).

    To the first it must be said that in the signification of a name there are two things to

    be considered, namely, that from which [id a quo] the name is imposed in order to signify,and that with respect to which [id ad quod] it is imposed in order to signify. But it

    sometimes happens that the substance of some thing is named by some accident which

    does not follow upon the whole nature of which that name is said, just as lapis, or stone,is said by reason of the fact that laedit pedem, it hurts the foot, still, neither is everything

    hurting the foot a stone, nor conversely. And so the judgement about a name ought not to

    be made according to that from which it is imposed, but according to that with respect to

    which it is established [instituitur] in order to signify.

    St. Thomas Aquinas, Qu. Disp. de Pot., q. 9, art. 3, ad 1 (tr. B.A.M.).

    To the first therefore it must be said that in any name there are two things to

    consider, namely, that with respect to which (id ad quod) the name is imposed in order to

    signify, and that from which [id a quo] it is imposed in order to signify. For often somename is imposed in order to signify some thing from some accident, whether an act or an

    effect of that thing; yet these things are not principally signified by that name

    [principaliter significata per illud nomen], but rather the very substance or nature of thething, just as the name lapis, stone, is taken from laesione pedis, the hurting of the foot,

    yet it does not signify this, but rather a certain body in which such an accident is often

    found. And so the hurting of the foot pertains to the etymology of the name rather than to

    its signification.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., IIa-IIae, q. 92, art. 1, ad 2 (tr. B.A.M.).

    14

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    15/24

    To the second it must be said that the etymology of a name [ etymologia nominis] is

    one thing, and the signification of a name [significatio nominis] is something else.Etymology is looked to according to that from which [id a quo] the name is imposed in

    order to signify, but the signification of the name according to that with respect to which

    [id ad quod] the name is imposed in order to signify. Sometimes these things are different;for the name lapis, stone, is imposed from laesione pedis, the hurting of the foot, yet it

    does not signify this, otherwise iron, since it also hurts the foot, would be a stone.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,In I Peri Herm., lect. 4, n. 9 (tr. B.A.M.).

    The reason is that one name is imposed in order to signify a simple concept; but

    that from which [id a quo] the name is imposed in order to signify is other than that which[eo quod] the name signifies, as the name lapis, stone, from laesione pedis, the hurting

    of the foot, which is not what the name signifies: which nevertheless is imposed in order

    to signify the concept of a certain thing.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,In I Sent., dist. 22, q. 1, art. 2, c. (tr. B.A.M.).

    But if we were to consider the thing signified in a name [rem significatam innomine], which is that with respect to which [id ad quod] a name is imposed in order to

    signify.

    15

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    16/24

    6. On to speak:

    St. Thomas Aquinas,In I Job, cap. I (tr. B.A.M.).

    Now one must know that to speak is taken in two ways. For sometimes it refers tothe concept of the heart, whereas other times it refers to the signification by which such a

    concept is expressed to another.1

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., q. 34, art. 1 ad 3 (tr. B.A.M.)

    For to speak is nothing other than to bring forth a word. 2

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., Ia, q. 2, art. 4, ad 1 (tr. B.A.M.).

    For when we understand a stone, that which the intellect conceives from the thingunderstood [ex re intellecta] is called a word [verbum].3

    7. In sum:

    Now one must know that to speak is taken in two ways. For sometimes it refers to

    the concept of the heart, whereas other times it refers to the signification by which such a

    concept is expressed to another. (St. Thomas Aquinas,In I Job, cap. I, tr. B.A.M.)

    For to speak is nothing other than to bring forth a word. (St. Thomas Aquinas,

    Summa Theol., q. 34, art. 1 ad 3, tr. B.A.M.)

    For when we understand a stone, that which the intellect conceives from the thingunderstood [ex re intellecta] is called a word [verbum].4 (St. Thomas Aquinas, SummaTheol., Ia, q. 2, art. 4, ad 1, tr. B.A.M.)

    For the idea signified by the name is the conception in the intellect of the thingsignified by the name. (St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theol., Ia, q. 13, art. 4.)

    ST1 SUMMAE THEOLOGIAE PRIMA PARS QU-2 AR-4RA-1

    ad primum ergo dicendum quod in his in quibus differt intellectus et intellectum, volens et volitum,

    potest esse realis relatio et scientiae ad rem scitam, et volentis ad rem volitam. sed in deo est idemomnino intellectus et intellectum, quia intelligendo se intelligit omnia alia, et eadem ratione

    voluntas et volitum. unde in deo huiusmodi relationes non sunt reales, sicut neque relatio eiusdem

    ad idem. sed tamen relatio ad verbum est realis, quia verbum intelligitur ut procedens per actionem

    intelligibilem, non autem ut res intellecta. cum enim intelligimus lapidem, id quod ex re intellecta

    concipit intellectus, vocatur verbum.

    1 ...sciendum autem est quod dicere dupliciter accipitur, nam quandoque refertur ad conceptum cordis,

    quandoque autem ad significationem qua huiusmodi conceptus alteri exprimitur.2nihil enim est aliud dicere quam proferre verbum.3cum enim intelligimus lapidem, id quod ex re intellecta concipit intellectus, vocatur verbum.4cum enim intelligimus lapidem, id quod ex re intellecta concipit intellectus, vocatur verbum.

    16

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    17/24

    8. On the difference between that from which and that upon which a name has been

    imposed in order to signify.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,In III Sent., dist. 6, q. 1, art. 3, c. (tr. B.A.M.).

    I reply that it must be said that in any name there are two things to consider,

    namely, that from which [id a quo] a name is imposed, which is called the quality of the

    name, and that upon which [id cui] it is imposed, which is called the substance

    11

    of thename.And a name, properly speaking, is said to signify [significare] the form or quality

    from which the name is imposed; but it is said to suppose on behalf of that upon which it is

    imposed [supponere pro eo cui imponitur].

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., q. 13, art. 11, ad 1 (tr. B.A.M.).

    To the first therefore it must be said that the name Qui est, He who is is a more

    proper name of God than the nameDeus, God, with respect to that from which [id a quo]

    it is imposed, namely, from esse, being or existing, and with respect to both the modeof signifying and of consignifying, as has been said. But with respect to that with respectto which [id ad quod] the name is imposed in order to signify, the name God is more

    proper because it is imposed in order to signify the divine nature. And a name more proper

    still is Tetragrammaton, which has been imposed in order to signify the very substance ofGod, incommunicable, and, if one may be allowed to speak so, singular.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., Ia, q. 13, art. 9, c. (tr. B.A.M.).

    But if there were some name imposed in order to signify God not on the part of the

    nature, but on the part of the supposit, insofar as it is considered as a this something [ hocaliquid], that name would be incommunicable in every way, as perhaps is the name

    Tetragrammaton among the Hebrews.

    9. That the ratio which a name signifies is what the name signifies.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., Ia, q. 13, art. 4, c. (tr. B.A.M.).

    For the ratio which the name signifies is the conception of the intellect of the thing

    signified by the name [de re significata per nomen].

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol., Ia, q. 2, art. 4, ad 1 (tr. B.A.M.).

    For when we understand a stone, that which the intellect conceives from the thingunderstood [ex re intellecta] is called a word [verbum].

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Resp. ad lect. vercell. de art. 108 (tr. B.A.M.).

    1Compare Summa Theol., Ia, q. 29, art. 2, c.: In another way the subject or supposit which subsists in the

    genus of substance is called substance. (alio modo dicitur substantia subiectum vel suppositum quod

    subsistit in genere substantiae).

    17

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    18/24

    First one must consider that the ratio of anything is what its name signifies, just as

    the ratio of a stone is what its name signifies. But names are signs of intellectual concept-tions: and so the ratio of each thing signified by the name is the conception of the intellect

    which the name signifies.

    But this conception of the intellect is indeed in the intellect as in a subject, but inthe thing understood as in a thing represented: for the conceptions of the intellect are

    certain likeness of things that have been understood. But if the conception of the intellect

    were not made into a likeness of the thing, the conception of that thing would be false, as ifone were to understand a stone to be what is not a stone. Therefore the ratio of a stone isindeed in the intellect as in a subject, but in the stone as in that which causes truth in the

    conception of the intellect of the one understanding the stone to be such. Therefore when

    the intellect comprehends a thing, it represents that thing perfectly by one conception. Andthus there happen to be diverse conceptions of diverse things.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theol. Ia, q. 13, art. 8 (tr. B.A.M.).

    And so because we can know the substance of a stone from its property according

    to itself [secundum se], by knowing what a stone is, the name stone signifies the verynature of a stone as it is in itself, for it signifies the definition of a stone by virtue of which

    we know what a stone is. For the ratio which the name signifies is the definition, as is said

    in the fourth book of theMetaphysics.

    St. Thomas Aquinas,In I Sent., dist. 2, q. 1, art. 3, c., tr. B.A.M.).

    One must bear in mind that ratio, as it is taken here, is nothing other than thatwhich the intellect apprehends from the signification of a name: and thisin those things

    which have a definitionis the definition itself of the thing, according to what the

    Philosopher says: the ratio which the name signifies is the definition. But some thingsare said to have a ratio in the way mentioned which are not defined, such as quantity and

    quality and the like, which, since they are the most general genera, are not defined. And

    nevertheless the ratio of quality is what is signified by the name of quality; and this is

    that from which quality has what quality is. For this reason, he does not refer to whetherthose things which are said to have a ratio either have or do not have a definition.

    Michael Augros, Philosophical and Theological Scrapbook. Summer 1994 (scrapboo

    5), Logic, n. 1.

    Accidentia. MEANINGS OF ACCIDENTIA. Posterior Analytics, Commentary, L.II,l.XIII, n 533. Sed quia formae essentiales non sunt nobis per se notae, oportet quod

    manifestentur per aliqua accidentia, quae sunt signa illius formae, ut patet in VIII

    Metaphysic.

    Accidentia here is taken according to the common meaning of anything

    belonging to something which is not itself part of the what. Hence properties in the

    strict sense would be accidentia in this sense. Going from sense to understanding, effectto cause, accident to substance, are all connected.

    18

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    19/24

    10. Charles De Koninck on matters concerning the impositions of names.

    Charles De Koninck, The Unity and Diversity of Natural Science, footnote 14.

    By natural language Prof. Heisenberg does not mean a language that is natural tous as our organs of speech are natural, as if nature provided us with a language the way

    that she produces feet and brain. Unless we call the grunts and groans of man or beast

    language, this term refers to artifacts that signify by convention.

    Using ordinary language we should always be able to refer its words back to

    common knowledge of things first known, a knowledge which may lead us to further

    knowledge of things, requiring either new impositions upon words already in use, or even,simply, a new word. An example of a new imposition would be the word soul, which

    first meant breeze or breath; an instance of a new word is Godno matter what its etym-

    ological originfor God can be known only at the term of a discourse, and once knownwe impose the name as entirely proper to Him. I do not mean that in doing so we spell out

    a new word. The point is that in virtue of the imposition the name now has a single mean-

    ing incommunicable to anything else, except by metaphor.

    Charles De Koninck, The Hollow Universe, Chapter III, The Lifeless World of

    Biology.

    Of all our normal language it is true that, whether its words be used as metaphors,

    given new meanings, or meanings long worn out and now revived, they still imply refer-

    ence to something already known, something that may be quite certain, no matter howfuzzy at the edges.

    Charles De Koninck, Abstraction from Matter, Part I, IV. What is meant by

    Matter in Abstraction from Matter?.

    2. Original meaning and etymology

    Now concerning the word matter, the original meaning we have in mind should be

    distinguished from the words origin or etymology,1 which is quite contingent.

    The etymology of a word is one thing, its meaning another. For its etymology shows that from

    which the word was taken for the purpose of signification [id a quo imponitur ad significandum]:

    whereas the meaning of the word concerns that upon which the word is imposedfor the purpose of

    signification [id ad quod significandum nomen imponitur]. These things are not always the same:

    for the name lapis is taken from laesio pedis,2 but this is not what it means; else iron, since it hurts

    the foot, would be a stone.3

    From the Greeketymologia: the real, true (etymon) or primitive meaning of a word.2 This etymology, reported by St. Isidore of Seville (cir. 570-636), is in fact incorrect.3IIa IIae, q. 92, a. 1, ad 2; Q. D. de Potentia, q. 9, a. 3, ad 1.

    Yet whatever the etymology of the word lapisor of our own wordstone, for that matter

    the meaning we are concerned with here would be that of lapis as the name of this kindof object to which we can point a finger, and not with the name as drawn from the

    19

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    20/24

    possibility of a stone affecting us in this way or that. A person may know the primary

    imposition of a word without knowing exactly how it came to get it in the etymologicalsense. For instance, the nameMetaphysics came to mean what it does in a very casual way.

    Because of the place assigned to themafter the Physicsby an early compiler of Aris-

    totles works, certain treatises were called Metaphysics: meta/ ta/ fusika/. This providesus with the etymology of the name, i.e., that whence the name was taken; whereas the

    primary imposition ofmetaphysica as a single word refers to treatises which, in the proper

    order of learning, are to be studied after those on nature. Eventually, by a new imposition,going beyond yet embracing the previous one, metaphysica, as Boethius (cir. 480-524)employed this term, referred to the science which Aristotle himself had called First Philo-

    sophy and TheologyFirst by reason of its principles, Theology because of its principal

    term, viz., knowledge of what is divine.1

    Of course, that from which the signification of the word is drawn or that whence

    the name is imposed, and that which the word signifies are sometimes the same, viz., inthe case of words conveying what is immediately known to our senses, such as hot, cold,

    hard, white,words which are verified directly by reference to sense experience, and

    which are in no other way verifiable. The reason for this resides in the fact that even of thethings which are present to our senses, and at any rate first and more known to us, we do

    not know directly what they are in themselves; this we can approach only through some-

    thing extrinsic to their nature, viz., some sensible effect or quality.2 What we first discern

    of a horse, for example, is what appears to the senses and allows us to tell it from a cow, orpig, etc. These colours, textures, sounds, we can name at once, and, in such instances, that

    from which the signification is drawn does not differ from whatthe name is intended to

    mean, although that to which these qualities belong is still not truly known as to what it isin itself absolutely.3

    But it is perhaps well to point out that these qualities or operations which lead to afirst attempt at naming a thing like a horse are not to be confused with the distinctive

    properties which truly set a horse apart from other things. Further knowledge may oblige

    us to change our minds about what constitute real differences. We may become acquainted

    with an animal like a zebra, let us say, possessing all the traits we had assigned as peculiarto the horse, and yet endowed with a few more of its own. What was thought to charac-

    terize a horse would now appear to be only something it has in common with certain other

    animals. In other words, if we assumed that we knew a given substance, e.g., a wood-pecker, as to what sets it apart from all other things absolutely, just because we knew the

    word woodpecker in its derivation from some other words previously formed to signify a

    substance and operations or effects of what we call a woodpecker, we would be like a manwho, understanding that bluefish is derived from blue plusfish, insisted that every blue fish

    ought to be a bluefish, and all bluefish blue. Such examples may seem somewhat out-

    landish, yet the confusion they illustrate is widespread among philosophers and evenamong their critics.4

    Outside the Aristotelian tradition, for centuries now the name metaphysics (as the adjective meta-

    physical) has had almost as many different meanings as there have been authors to use it, its

    etymology being the only common aspect of the word to survive.2Ia Pars, q. 13, a. 6, c. [N.B. The reference should be to the corpus of article 8.B.A.M.]3 Obvious examples of substance-names taken from a perceptible quality or action already named

    would be quicksilverorrattlesnake; they do not signify the fluidity of mercury or the rattle of a

    20

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    21/24

    certain type of snake. The word snake is another example, being kin to sneak, as well as to the Old

    Germansnachan, to creep.

    4 The criticisms leveled against philosophical jargon by the logical positivists are only too often

    well taken and should be turned to advantage.

    To cling to the first impositions as the only valid ones may be just as foolish as to lose one-

    self in vague, extended meanings without comprehending the basic imposition to which

    these may owe their force.

    3.Names that are not taken from other things

    It should be noted, however, that names signifying substances, such as man, horse,

    tree,stone, etc., can never have the immediate meanings of words like noise,smell,sweet,

    pain, large, smooth, inside, feel, move, etc. Terms like these are the most basic in anylanguage. Whatever their philological origin, they are not named from other things: that

    which they mean is the same as that from which their signification is drawn. Now the fact

    that this identity holds only in the case of objects immediately known by our senses 1

    should make us aware of how important it is to take into account what happens in the

    knower between his apprehension of a thing and his naming of it. Different words areintended to signify different things. But the differences indicated by variations in names

    are seldom the proper differences which set the things themselves apart from one another.If the knower, who imposes a meaning upon a word, does not actually attain the essential

    differences between the things named, he may in his naming of them, refer to some trait

    which, though admittedly not the essential difference, is used instead of itas in the namerattlesnake. If we assumed that the warning sound referred to in this name, which is that

    whence it was imposed, was actually whatthe name meant, we would imply, gratuitously,

    that this sound was the essential difference of that which we name.2 To sum up, if theessential differences between things were grasped at once, the differences of names would

    be taken from them: that whence they signify would be that which they signifythe speci-

    fic differences of the things themselves. The whole relevance of the distinction between thespecific difference of the thing itself and the trait from which the things name is takenderives from the fact that we do not know outright the essential differences of things, and

    that we can name things only as we know them.3

    As we shall see in Part II, chap. 3, there is a notable difference between interpreting a word like

    horse by pointing to such an animal, and interpreting the word white by designating a white horse.What we call white is something sensibleper se, whereas a white horse, as a substance, is sensible

    onlyper accidensas we shall explain further on.2 The word rattlesnake may, as a composite name, be used to confirm the distinction between

    etymology and signification. For, that which the name signifies, is not the two things called rattleandsnake, these being only that from which the name has been imposed. The components of this

    name can signify separately, but they cease to do so when taken together as one name. The reason

    is that a single name is imposed to signify a simple concept; for, that whence the name is imposed

    to signify is not the same as that which the name signifies, as lapis from laesio pedis, which is not

    what the name signifies: for it was imposed to mean the concept of a thing. Hence it is that a part of

    the composite name imposed to signify a simple concept, does not signify part of the composite

    conception from which the name was imposed to signify. An expression [e.g., pale man] signifies

    the composite conception itself: hence a part of the expression signifies the composite conception

    (St. Thomas,In I Perih., lect. 4, n. 9).

    21

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    22/24

    3 That a name is said to be imposed from something can be taken [a] either on the part of the one

    who imposes it, or [b] on the part of the thing upon which it is imposed. In the latter case, a name is

    said to be imposed from that which completes the notion of the thing it signifies, viz., the specific

    difference of the thing [i.e. that which sets it apart from other things]. However, since the essential

    differences are unknown to us, we sometimes use accidents or effects in their steadand name the

    things accordingly. And thus it is that, whatever is used to take the place of the essential differences

    is also that whence the name is imposed, considered on the part of the one who imposes the

    meaning: as when lapis is imposed from an effect, laedere pedem. And this need not be that which

    the word is intended to mean before all; the word means that instead of which we use the effect[viz., laedere pedem] (St. Thomas, Q. D. de Veritate, q. 4, a. 1, ad 8).

    However, though, the relationship between meaning and etymology should not be

    confused with the dependence of a new and extended imposition upon a prior meaning, itmust not be thought that knowledge of a words origin is of importance only to the philol-

    ogist. Etymology, providing as it does a kind of reason why a given word was formed and

    used to signify this or that, has the advantage of referring us to something known evenbefore the first imposition of that word. For instance, the verb to manifestmeaning to

    show plainly, to make appear distinctly, to put beyond question or doubtcomes from

    the Latin manifestare which was originally taken from manus, hand, andfendere, to sieze;

    fur manifestus meant a thief caught in the act. This word, then, referred originally to themost basic of our external senses: to touch, and to the palpable.

    Michael A. Augros, Scrapboo.5. n. 34.

    34) WE DO NOT KNOW THE SUBSTANTIAL FORMS OF THINGS. From De Spiritu-

    alibus Creaturis (Q1 A11 Ad3), in answer to the objection that the powers of the soul mustbe substance, since we use the powers as substantial differences, St. Thomas says:

    Ad tertium dicendum quod formae substantiales per seipsas sunt ignotae; sedinnotescunt nobis per accidentia propria. Frequenter enim differentiae substantiales ab

    accidentibus sumuntur, loco formarum substantialium, quae per huiusmodi accidentiainnotescunt; sicut bipes et gressibile et huiusmodi; et sic etiam sensibile et rationaleponuntur differentiae substantiales. Vel potest dici, quod sensibile et rationale, prout sunt

    differentiae, non sumuntur a ratione et a sensu secundum quod nominant potentias, sed ab

    anima rationali, et ab anima sensitiva.

    11. On the proper and common sensibles.

    Cf. Michael Augros, Notes from the Berquist Seminars (Duane.2), nn. 232; 237-

    238:

    232) MISTAKES IN THE SENSES AND IN REASON n 385. The senses do not makemistakes about the first things they know, their own private sensibles, but only about the

    common sensibles they know through their private sensibles. This is like reason, which

    doesnt make mistakes about the first things it knows (e.g. the axioms), but only about the

    things it knows through the first things it knows.

    237) DIVISION OF SENSIBLES DO NOT CORRESPOND TO CATEGORIES. Are the

    five common sensibles and the various proper sensibles divided in a way that fits with the

    22

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    23/24

    division of the categories? The proper sensibles are all in the third species of quality. Of

    the common sensibles, figure is in the fourth species of quality. Number and size are in thecategory of quantity. Motion and rest are all over the place. Hence, the division of sensi-

    bles into private and common sensibles does not correspond to the division of the

    categories. The categories are distinguished by the ways (or figures, as Aristotle says) ofpredication, whereas the common and private sensibles are distinguished in a different

    way.

    238) COMMON SENSIBLES IMPORTANT TO WHOLE LIFE OF MIND. Commonsensibles are more the basis of knowing other things than are the private sensibles. Hence

    we carry over names such as form from the common sensibles to many other things,

    some of which are not even sensible at all. But what role does green play in the life ofthe mind? When St. Thomas is commenting on Boethiuss De Trinitate, he answers an ob-

    jection that we cannot know God because the human mind understands nothing without the

    continuous and time by saying we can know him by negating these. Hence we can knowthat God is not a body, and not in time; we are still understanding God with the continuous

    and time, since one must understand what one is negating. But notice that the continuous

    and time are common sensibles, or based on common sensibles, such as size and motion.No one could object that we cannot understand anything without proper sensibles, e.g.

    green and sweet.

    Michael Augros, Summer 1993 Scrapbook. Philosophy And Theology (Scrapboo.2), n.

    3:

    [3] Mind alone can be the cause of order, i.e. intellectual knowledge, and not senseknowledge. For the senses cannot know order: I cannot sense the order of one thing to

    another, but only the separate things in the order. Therefore the cause of order must be

    mind. But why is it proper to a mind to grasp relation or the proportion of one thing toanother? Why cant the senses grasp relation? If any relation is sensible, most assuredly the

    relations between magnitudes are, e.g. larger than. If larger than is a sensible, then it

    should be a common sensible, since the terms in the relation (two sizes) are themselves

    common sensibles. Now why are common sensibles, such as size and shape, regarded asper se sensibles at all? After all, we see the size only through the color. Because a different

    size really affects the sight differently. It physically acts on the sense organ. Likewise

    motion is a per se sensible, although common, because it really affects the sensesdifferently (motion sooner catches the eye than what not stirs). Do different relations do

    this? If I see three objects at once, A, B, C, and B is larger than A but smaller than C, then

    B is at once larger and smaller (with respect to different things), so there are two relationshere, but my sight is not affected differently by them: B does not look differently because

    of the two relations. Therefore relation is not a per se sensible, but only sensible per

    accidens. It does not affect the senses at all, and so it is not an object of the senses. Hencemind alone can know relation, and so mind alone can know order, and so mind alone can

    know in particular the order of means to ends, and so mind alone can guide and direct

    natures to their ends

    23

  • 7/28/2019 Some Principles in the Art of Naming.

    24/24

    12. Some examples of the principles of names taken from St. Thomas.

    The name Trinitas, Trinity.

    that from which: ipso numero qui in nomine importatur, the very number impliedin the name, which is trium unitas, a unity of three things

    that with respect to which: tres personae unius essentiae, three Persons of oneessence, ornumerum personarum unius essentiae, a number of Persons of one essence,ornumerum personarum ad invicem relatarum, a number of Persons related to each other

    The name Qui Est, He who is.

    that from which: esse, being or existing

    The nameDeus, God.

    that from which: universalis rerum providentia, the universal providence ofthings

    that with respect to which: natura divina, the divine nature

    The name Tetragrammaton.

    that with respect to which (and also that upon which, although not in the samerespect): ipsam dei substantiam incommunicabilem et singularem, the incommunicable

    and singular substance of God Himself

    The name ens, (a) being.

    that from which: actus essendi, the act of being

    The name unum, one.

    that from which ordo, order, or indivisio, being undivided; for one is ensindivisum, undivided being

    The name lapis, stone.

    that from which: quod laedit pedem, what hurts the foot, inasmuch as hurting

    is an operatio oreffectus of a stone

    that with respect to which: the definition of a stone, which is the ratio signified by

    the name, which is a certain species of body

    (c) 2013 Bart A. Mazzetti. All rights reserved.