time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain a. c. dennett and m....

32
Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Upload: louis-salyers

Post on 01-Apr-2015

218 views

Category:

Documents


5 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain

A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Page 2: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Is there a “central observer” in the brain?

A Problem: to decide what to count as the “finishing line” in the brain.

Page 3: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

The wrong ideas

There is some place in the brain where “it all comes together” in a multi-modal representation or display.

The representation or display is definitive of the content of conscious experience.

The temporal properties of the events (representations) determine the temporal properties of the subjective “stream of consciousness.”

Page 4: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Dennett’s main point

There is no one place in the brain through which all these causal trains must pass to deposit their contents “in consciousness.”

Page 5: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Dennett’s main claim

The brain itself is Headquarters, the place where the ultimate observer is, but it is a mistake to believe that the brain has any deeper headquarters arrival at which is the necessary or sufficient condition for conscious experience.

Page 6: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Cartesian materialism

The idea of there being a centered locus in the brain

Cartesian theater model of consciousness

Page 7: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Multiple drafts model

Massively parallel operations

Distributed activation patterns

These patterns are drafts which are undergone constant editing

Page 8: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Some temporal anomalies

Color phi

The cutaneous “Rabbit”

Referral backwards in time

Subjective delay of consciousness of intention

Page 9: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

How does the brain keep track of the temporal information?

How to achieve synchrony?

Two models:

Delay loop mechanism

Buffer memories

Page 10: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Representations of temporal properties

The battle of New Orleans

Solution to the problems of communicating information about time:

by embedding representations of the relevant time information in the content of their signals

Page 11: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Time represented: by the postmark

Time of representing: the day the letter arrives

Page 12: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

What matters is the temporal content of events.

Page 13: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

How are temporal properties really inferred by the brain?

Content-sensitive settling (such as film studio case)

It is not necessary to use time to represent time.

Page 14: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

The striking fact … should be noticed, namely that perceptions of temporal order need temporally ordered perceptions.

Perception of shape and color, for example, need not themselves be correspondingly shaped or colored.

(Mellor 1981)

Page 15: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

The Orwellian and Stalinesque revisions: the illusion of a distinction

Page 16: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Orwellian: post-experiential contaminations or revisions of memory

Stalineque: pre-experiential revision

Page 17: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Dennett’s point

The distinction between perceptual revisions and memory revisions that works crisply at other scales is not guaranteed application.We have moved into the foggy area in which the subject’s point of view is spatially and temporally smeared.The question Oewellian or Stalinque? Need have no answer.

Page 18: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

If Cartesian materialism were correct, this question would have to have an answer, even if we could not introspect it.

Page 19: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

If Cartesian materialism is incorrect, can the distinction between pre- and post-experiential content revisions be maintained?

Page 20: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

An examination of the color phi phenomenon shows that the distinction cannot be maintained.

Page 21: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Anomalies about Time

Color Phi phenomenon

Page 22: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Dennett’s comment

There is only the verbal difference between the two theories

Page 23: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Libet’s two remarkable temporal factors

There is a substantial delay before cerebral activities, initiated by a sensory stimulus, achieve “neural adequacy” for eliciting any resulting sensory experience (500 msec)After neural adequacy is achieved, the subjective timing of the experience is referred backwards in time, utilizing a “timing signal.”

Page 25: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Basic idea of the experiment

We ask subject to report the subjective timing of an ordinary stimulus to the skin and a cortically induced sensation.

Page 26: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

(1) A continuous stimulus train at 60 pulses per second was applied to sensory cortex. (C)

(2) A single pulse at threshold to the skin of the arm 200 msec later. (S)

(3) C-experience was reported to occur approximately 500 msec after stimulation began.

(2’) In fact it was reported to occur at approximately the time of the skin pulse, before the C-experience. (4) We might expect S-

experience to occur 200 msec after C-experience.

Page 27: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Cortical stimulus

O ms 200ms

The skin stimulus

This finding led Libet to propose the “subjective referral of sensory experience backwards in time”

210-220 ms

Conscious experience of the skin stimulus was reported.

500ms

Conscious experience of the cortical stimulus was reported.

700ms

Conscious experience of the skin stimulus was reported.

Page 28: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

If half a second of neural activity is required for conscious perception, why is the skin stimulus felt first?

?

Page 29: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

The backwards referral hypothesisLibet

Sensory experience are subjectively referred back in time once neuronal adequacy has been achieved.

Page 30: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

1. Information travels from the skin up to the relevant sensory area of cortex.

2. If ,and only if, neural activity continues there for the requisite half a second, the stimulus can be consciously perceived.

3. At that point it is subjectively referred back to the actual time at which it happened.

The backwards referral hypothesisSteps

Page 31: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

Stimulate sensorimotor cortex

O ms 200ms

Stimulate the skin

Combine the experiment (3) and (4)(3) indicate by blue; (4) indicate by red

210-220 ms

Conscious experience of the stimulus of skin was reported.

500ms

Conscious experience of the stimulus of sensorimotor cortex was reported.

Stimulate medial lemniscus

Conscious experience of the stimulus of medial lemniscus was reported.

One of the special features of medial lemniscus when it is stimulated:Unlike the cortex, a primary evoked potential is also produced, just as it is when the skin itself is stimulated.

Page 32: Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain A. C. Dennett and M. Kinsbourne

The primary evoked potential act as a timing signal to which the sensation is referred back or “antedated”.