understanding regulation. theory, strategy, and practice

563

Upload: ana-p-gil

Post on 17-Sep-2015

272 views

Category:

Documents


35 download

DESCRIPTION

Regulation Book

TRANSCRIPT

  • Understanding Regulation

    Second Edition

  • This page intentionally left blank

  • UnderstandingRegulationTheory, Strategy, and Practice

    Second Edition

    Robert Baldwin, Martin Cave, Martin Lodge

    1

  • 3Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp

    Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.It furthers the Universitys objective of excellence in research, scholarship,and education by publishing worldwide in

    Oxford New York

    Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong KarachiKuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City NairobiNew Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto

    With ofces in

    Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France GreeceGuatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal SingaporeSouth Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam

    Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Pressin the UK and in certain other countries

    Published in the United Statesby Oxford University Press Inc., New York

    # Robert Baldwin, Martin Cave, and Martin Lodge 2012

    The moral rights of the authors have been assertedDatabase right Oxford University Press (maker)

    First edition published 2012

    All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press,or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriatereprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproductionoutside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,Oxford University Press, at the address above

    You must not circulate this book in any other binding or coverand you must impose this same condition on any acquirer

    British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data

    Data available

    Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data

    Data available

    Typeset by SPI Publisher Services, Pondichery, IndiaPrinted in Great Britainon acid-free paper byMPG Books Group, Bodmin and Kings Lynn

    ISBN 9780199576081 (Hbk)ISBN 9780199576098 (Pbk)

    1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2

  • n ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

    We are grateful to a number of individuals for their help with this book. For

    research assistance, textual comments, and work on manuscripts, we thank

    Vanessa Finch, Amanda Tinnams, and Emma Wilson.

    We also express our appreciation to all of those colleagues at LSE who have

    assisted in a variety of ways in the production of this textand, not least we

    thank colleagues with whom we have taught on the LSEs M.Sc. in Regulation

    and on the LSEs Short Course on Regulation. Martin Lodge would like

    particularly to acknowledge the support of the ESRC Centre for Analysis of

    Risk and Regulation. We are grateful also to the colleagues with whom we

    have co-authored or co-edited works on regulation and who have allowed us

    to draw on those publications in writing this book. We thank in particular

    Tony Ballance, Julia Black, Damian Chalmers, Veerle Heyvaert, Ian Marlee,

    Henry Rothstein, and Lindsay Stirton.

  • This page intentionally left blank

  • n PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

    Since the rst edition of Understanding Regulation was published in 1999, the

    practice and study of regulation has changed dramatically. Politically, there

    have been shifts from emphases on deregulation to better regulation and

    back again. There have been calls for lowerings of regulatory burdens on

    businesses and for increasing resort to lighter-touch regulatory systems and

    regimes that delegate controls to businesses. These calls fell silent after the

    start of the credit crisis of 20079, but they can be expected to re-emerge in

    coming years. The legacy of such movements and political fashions has,

    however, been a developed interest in non-traditional strategies of regula-

    tionin methods of inuence that constitute alternatives to command and

    control. Newly popular devicessuch as nudginghave found their way on

    to politicians agendas and there have been redoubled concerns to debate such

    issues as the legitimacy of different regulatory systems and approaches.

    Regulatory studies and theories have also progressed signicantly over the

    past dozen years. Regulation has become the subject of discrete courses and

    degree programmes around the world and new journals have emerged to deal

    with the subject. Most disciplines now provide numbers of scholars who see

    regulation as a primary area of research and teaching. As a result, a host of

    new theories and perspectives have been brought to bear on regulation and

    have enriched understandings.

    This edition seeks to come to grips with all of the newer develop-

    ments referred to. In doing so, it continues the broad approach of the rst

    edition and sees regulation as a subject that is best understood from a multi-

    disciplinary perspective. The addition of Martin Lodge, a political scientist, as

    co-author is a happy furthering of this position.

    Robert Baldwin, Martin Cave,

    and Martin Lodge,

    March 2011

  • This page intentionally left blank

  • n CONTENTS

    LIST OF FIGURES xi

    LIST OF TABLES xii

    ABBREVIATIONS xiii

    1 Introduction 1

    PART I FUNDAMENTALS

    2 Why Regulate? 15

    3 What is Good Regulation? 25

    4 Explaining Regulation 40

    5 Regulatory Failure 68

    6 Regulating Risks 83

    PART II STRATEGIES

    7 Regulatory Strategies 105

    8 Self-regulation, Meta-regulation, and Regulatory Networks 137

    9 Franchising 165

    10 Emissions Trading 195

    PART III RULES AND ENFORCEMENT

    11 Enforcing Regulation 227

    12 Responsive Regulation 259

    13 Risk-based Regulation 281

    14 Standards and Principles 296

    PART IV QUALITY AND EVALUATION

    15 Cost-Benet Analysis and Regulatory Impact Assessment 315

    16 Accountability, Procedures, and Fairness 338

    17 Regulatory Competition and Coordination 356

  • PART V REGULATION AT DIFFERENT LEVELS OF GOVERNMENT

    18 Multi-level Regulation 373

    19 Regulation and the European Union 388

    20 Regulation and Development 409

    21 Global and International Regulation 425

    PART VI NETWORK ISSUES

    22 Regulating Prices in Natural Monopolies 443

    23 Using Competition in Network Industries 452

    24 Separation and Contestability in Network Industries 466

    25 Implementing Price Controls 476

    26 Efciency and Innovation in Network Industries 492

    PART VII CONCLUSIONS

    27 Conclusions 505

    SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY 509

    INDEX 531

    x CONTENTS

  • n LIST OF FIGURES

    11.1 Regulatory tasks: the DREAM framework 227

    12.1 The enforcement pyramid 260

    12.2 The enforcement strategies pyramid 261

    12.3 The three aspects of smart regulation 266

    18.1 Four views on multi-level regulation 381

    22.1 Average and marginal cost in a natural monopoly 445

    22.2 Pricing options for a natural monopolist 447

    22.3 Efcient pricing for a multi-service utility 449

    24.1 Alternative forms of separation 468

    25.1 A simplied nancial model of the regulated rm used to

    set a price cap 484

    26.1 The effect on project choice of truncating high returns 493

    26.2 Identifying the efciency frontier 499

  • n LIST OF TABLES

    2.1 Rationales for regulating 24

    3.1 Benchmarks for regulation 39

    4.1 Variants in interest group politics 48

    4.2 Contrasting control styles according to cultural theory 51

    4.3 Explaining regulation 67

    5.1 Regulatory failure 77

    7.1 Regulatory strategies: posited strengths and weaknesses 134

    9.1 Allocating franchises 193

    9.2 Franchising problems 194

    16.1 Regulatory regimes and perspectives on accountability 353

    21.1 Variations in global regulation 427

    23.1 Competitive potential in electricity, gas, posts, railways,

    telecommunications, and water and sewerage 457

    25.1 Implementing a price cap regime: an illustration 479

    25.2 An illustrative timetable for resetting a price cap 482

    25.3 Selected price caps operating in the UK utilities 483

  • n ABBREVIATIONS

    ALARA As Low as Reasonably Achievable

    ALARP As Low as Reasonably Practicable

    BATNEEC Best Available Technology Not Entailing Excessive Costs

    BAU Business as Usual

    BCC British Chambers of Commerce

    BRE Better Regulation Executive

    BRTF Better Regulation Task Force

    BT British Telecom

    C & C Command and Control

    CAA Civil Aviation Authority

    CBA Cost-Benet Analysis

    CDM Clean Development Mechanism

    CRI Centre for the Study of Regulated Industries

    DAB Digital Audio Broadcasting

    DG Director General

    DGES Director General of Electricity Supply

    DTI Department of Trade and Industry

    ECJ European Court of Justice

    EMS Environmental Management System

    EPA Environment Protection Agency (US)

    ESRC Economic and Social Research Council

    ETS Emission Trading Scheme

    EU European Union

    EUI European University Institute (at Florence)

    FCCC Framework Convention on Climate Change

    GAAR General Anti-avoidance Rules

    HSE Health and Safety Executive

    IA Impact Assessment

    ILR Independent Local Radio

    ITA Independent Television Authority

    ITC Independent Television Commission

    JBL Journal of Business Law

  • MLR Modern Law Review

    MMC Monopolies and Mergers Commission

    NAO National Audit Ofce

    NCC National Consumer Council

    NRA National Regulatory Agency

    OFFER Ofce of Electricity Regulation

    OFGAS Ofce of Gas Supply

    OFGEM Ofce of the Gas and Electricity Markets

    OFT Ofce of Fair Trading

    OFTEL Ofce of Telecommunications

    OFWAT Ofce of Water Services

    OJLS Oxford Journal of Legal Studies

    OMB Ofce of Management and Budget

    OMC Open Method of Coordination

    ONP Open Network Provision

    ORR Ofce of the Rail Regulator

    PBR Principles-based Regulation

    PCC Press Complaints Commission

    PIG Public Interest Group

    RA Radio Authority

    RAB Regulatory Asset Base

    RCBA Risk Cost Benet Analysis

    REC Regional Electricity Company

    RIA Regulatory Impact Analysis

    ROSCO Rolling Stock Leasing Company

    RPI-X Retail Price Index less efciency factor X price cap

    SFAIRP So Far As Is Reasonably Practicable

    SME Small and Medium Enterprises

    TOR Tolerability of Risks

    TUC Trades Union Congress

    xiv ABBREVIATIONS

  • 1 Introduction

    Our aim in writing this book is to introduce readers to those practical and

    theoretical issues that we see as central to the study of regulation. We set out

    to describe the nature of those issues, to indicate how regulatory practitioners

    and scholars have dealt with them and to offer arguments on potential

    responses to regulatory difculties. The focus is not on providing how to

    accounts of regulatory experience. Instead, our aim is to highlight the con-

    tested areas and issues that are produced by regulation. We hope that this

    volume will add to exchanges between different viewpoints. Many of the

    examples in this book draw on the British experience, but we aim to make

    the text relevant to a wider international audience interested in regulatory

    activities broadly dened.

    Over the past decades, regulation has been a topic that has stimulated

    discussions in a host of disciplinesnotably law, economics, political science

    and public policy, sociology, history, psychology, geography, anthropology,

    management, and social administration. Given this breadth of interest, regu-

    lation is a subject or eld of study that calls for a multi-disciplinary approach.

    Economists, for instance, are likely to benet from the insights of political

    scientists and sociologists on such matters as the practicalities of implemen-

    tation and enforcement. Similarly, lawyers messages concerning the limita-

    tions of different kinds of rules and enforcement processes might protably be

    taken on board by economists and others. Analogous points could be made

    from the perspectives of other disciplines. This edition is written by a lawyer,

    an economist, and a political scientist, but will attempt both to draw from a

    wider range of disciplinary perspectives and to be accessible across disciplines.

    Highly technical approaches and terminology will be avoided where possible.

    It is hoped, therefore, that the analysis offered will prove useful to regulatory

    studies in a wide variety of areas.

    Regulation has become a matter of topical debate in a way that it was not

    even a single decade ago. This global phenomenon was partly prompted by

    the activities of international organizations. Criticisms and concerns with

    regulatory orthodoxies became increasingly prominent during the nancial

    crisis of 20079, when calls for deregulation and light-touch regulation

    suddenly gave way to daily demands for more rigorous regulation of the

    nancial markets. Elsewhere, too, regulation had attracted supporters and

    opponents alike. Supporters saw regulation as a technocratic device that had

    the potential to exert rational controls over important economic and social

    activities. Sceptics regarded regulation as little other than red tape and a

    potential burden on economic activity.

  • It is, therefore, fair to say that by 2011, the claim that we are living in an age

    of the regulatory state had become widely accepted as the R-word had

    penetrated ever more social domains across countries.1 Over the past decade,

    regulation has risen in the academic agenda to become both a eld of study in

    its own right and a fertile source of new perspectives on the agendas of longer-

    established disciplines. Substantial contributions to regulatory debates have

    been made by political scientists, economists, lawyers, sociologists, anthro-

    pologists, and others. Writings on regulation have become well-represented

    across scholarly publications, and a diversity of university courses and pro-

    grammes, as well as research centres, have emerged to deal with various

    aspects of the theory and practice of regulation. Some of these have treated

    regulation as a generic subject taught in interdisciplinary programmes; others

    have specialized in specic areas, such as nancial services, environmental

    protection, communications, or utilities.

    As a consequence, regulation can be said now to have reached a state of

    maturity, both in an intellectual and in a practical sense.2 Intellectually,

    theoretical perspectives have developed rapidly into an impressive body of

    scholarship and, in the world of practice, there has developed a distinct and

    expanding international and national regulatory community that shares

    similar languages, concepts, and concerns. The language of regulation has

    penetrated diverse policy domains and talk of regulatory strategy has become

    part of administrative life. In this process, central regulatory issues such as

    those relating to standard-setting and enforcement have become matters of

    regular discussion in different policy and academic communities.

    What is Regulation?

    Regulation is often spoken of as if an identiable and discrete mode of

    governmental activity,3 yet the term regulation has been dened in a number

    of ways.4 Selznicks notion of regulation as sustained and focused control

    1 See M. Moran, The British Regulatory State (Oxford, 2003); Understanding the Regulatory State

    (2002) 32 British Journal of Political Science 391413; and contrast this with G. Majone, The Rise of

    the Regulatory State in Europe (1994) 17(3) West European Politics 77101.2 For comparison with the position a decade ago see R. Baldwin, C. Scott, and C. Hood,

    Introduction in R. Baldwin, C. Scott, and C. Hood (eds), A Reader on Regulation (Oxford, 1998).

    See also R. Baldwin, M. Cave, and M. Lodge, Introduction in R. Baldwin, M. Cave, and M. Lodge(eds.), Oxford Handbook of Regulation (Oxford, 2010).

    3 See Baldwin, Scott, and Hood, Regulation, ch. 1.4 See B. Mitnick, The Political Economy of Regulation (New York, 1980), ch. 1; A. Ogus, Regulation:

    Legal Form and Economic Theory (Oxford, 1994), ch. 1; G. Majone (ed.), De-Regulation or

    Re-Regulation? (London, 1989).

    2 INTRODUCTION

  • exercised by a public agency over activities that are valued by a community

    has been referred to as expressing a central meaning,5 but it is perhaps useful

    to think of the word regulation being used in the following different senses:6

    As a specic set of commandswhere regulation involves the promulgation

    of a binding set of rules to be applied by a body devoted to this purpose. An

    example would be the health and safety at work legislation as applied by the

    Health and Safety Executive.

    As deliberate state inuencewhere regulation has a more broad sense and

    covers all state actions that are designed to inuence business or social

    behaviour. Thus, command-based regimes would come within this usage,

    but so also would a range of other modes of inuencefor instance, those

    based on the use of economic incentives7 (e.g. taxes or subsidies); contractual

    powers; deployment of resources; franchises; the supply of information, or

    other techniques.

    As all forms of social or economic inuencewhere all mechanisms

    affecting behaviourwhether these be state-based or from other sources

    (e.g. markets)are deemed regulatory. One of the great contributions of

    the theory of smart regulation has been to point out that regulation

    may be carried out not merely by state institutions but by a host of

    other bodies, including corporations, self-regulators, professional or trade

    bodies, and voluntary organizations.8 According to this third, broad usage

    of the term regulation, there is no requirement that the regulatory effects of

    a mechanism are deliberate or designed, rather than merely incidental to

    other objectives.

    As a nal comment on the concept of regulation, it should be noted

    that regulation is often thought of as an activity that restricts behaviour

    and prevents the occurrence of certain undesirable activities (a red light

    concept9). The broader view is, however, that the inuence of regulation may

    also be enabling or facilitative (green light) as, for example, where the

    airwaves are regulated so as to allow broadcasting operations to be conducted

    in an ordered fashion, rather than left to the potential chaos of an uncon-

    trolled market.

    5 P. Selznick, Focusing Organisational Research on Regulation, in R. Noll (ed.), Regulatory Policy

    and the Social Sciences (Berkeley, CA, 1985), 363, quoted Ogus, Regulation, 1.6 See Baldwin, Scott, and Hood, Regulation, ch. 1; J. Black, Critical Reections on Regulation

    (2002) 27 Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 195.7 On the distinction between command-and incentive-based regimes, see S. Breyer, Regulation and

    Its Reform (Cambridge, MA, 1982); Ogus, Regulation, esp. ch. 11; and R. Baldwin, Regulation: After

    Command and Control, in K. Hawkins (ed.), The Human Face of Law (Oxford, 1997).8 See N. Gunningham and P. Grabosky, Smart Regulation (Oxford, 1998).9 On red light and green light rules and regulations, see C. Harlow and R. Rawlings, Law and

    Administration (3rd edn, Cambridge, 2009); Ogus, Regulation, 2.

    INTRODUCTION 3

  • Issues on the Regulatory Agenda

    There is a tendency to associate regulation with the post-privatization control

    of the utilities. The language and practice of regulation, however, looks back

    on a much longer history. In Britain, regulation has been practised since at

    least the Tudor and Stuart periods.10 In the nineteenth century, there was

    a burgeoning of regulation, with the emergence of specialist regulatory

    institutions11 and a host of measures dealing with public health and employ-

    ment conditions.12 Developments in the supply of railway, water, gas, and

    electricity services led to the introduction of controls over prices, safety,

    and quality of service.13 Elsewhere, too, regulation was practised widely and

    transferred from one domain to another. For example, initial railway regula-

    tion drew on provisions governing turnpikes.

    During the twentieth century, a steady growth in regulation took

    place from the 1930s onwards. That decade saw the licensing of goods and

    passenger carryings by road as well as the advent, in the shing industry, of

    marketing boards that fullled both operational and regulatory functions.

    The nationalization of core industries, such as the railways, were even framed

    as issues of regulation. For example, the godfather of the UK public corpor-

    ation model post-1945, Herbert Morrison, dened the ministerial func-

    tion vis-a`-vis public corporations as being regulatory and supervisory in

    character.14

    In the post-war period, marketing boards followed in the cotton, croft-

    ing, sugar, and iron and steel industries, and the rst US-style independent

    regulatory agency was established in Britain in 1954 with the Independent

    Television Authority.15 The ITA was innovatory in combining a degree of

    independence from government with the carrying out of adjudicatory and

    regulatory, as well as policy-developing, functions. In the United States,

    such independent regulatory bodies had been carrying out key functions of

    government since the Inter State Commerce Commission was established

    in 1887 to limit discriminatory pricing by railroads. In the ITAs wake

    followed a series of regulatory agencies that were created in the 1960s and

    10 Ogus, Regulation, 612; Regulatory Law: Some Lessons from the Past (1992) 12 Legal Studies 1.11 O. MacDonagh, The Nineteenth-Century Revolution in Government: A Reappraisal (1958)

    1 Historical Journal 52.12 P. Craig, Administrative Law (5th edn, London, 2003), ch. 2.13 See J. Foreman-Peck and R. Millward, Public and Private Ownership of British Industry

    18201990 (Oxford, 1994), esp. chs 13; C. Foster, Privatisation, Public Ownership and the Regulationof Natural Monopoly (Oxford, 1992), chs. 1 and 2.

    14 H. Morrison, Taking Stock, PRO MT 47/15, S.I. (M) (47) (32), 18 July 1947. See also M. Lodge,

    On Different Tracks (Westport, CT, 2002).15 B. Sendall, Independent Television in Britain: Origin and Foundation, vol. 1: 194662 (London,

    1982).

    4 INTRODUCTION

  • 1970s to deal with issues in such areas as monopolies, gaming, industrial

    relations, civil aviation, discrimination, and workplace health and safety.

    During the 1980s and 1990s, much stress was placed by governments and

    commentators on the problems and costs of regulation and the case for

    deregulating the economy.16 The privatization drive of the same period,

    however, produced a new burst of regulation, carried out by a host of new

    regulatory bodies such as OFTEL (1984), OFGAS (1986), OFFER (1989),

    OFWAT (1990), and the Ofce of the Rail Regulator (1993). In addition,

    administrative changes produced a new Environment Agency in 1996 and

    from the creation of the National Lottery there emerged an Ofce of the

    National Lottery to oversee the providing private operator, Camelot.

    By the mid-1990s, some 25 million customers were served by the main four

    regulated utilities industries alone. Their total annual turnover of 51 billion

    represented around 8 per cent of the annual gross domestic product of the

    UK, and not only the results of regulation but the processes used to regulate

    had prompted unprecedented concern. Regulation and deregulation had

    moved to positions high on the political agenda. Conservative administra-

    tions had sought, since 1985, to deregulate, cut red tape, and substitute

    competitive pressures for regulatory action. The Department of Trade and

    Industrys Enterprise and Deregulation Unit had been established in that year

    in order to review all new legislative instruments and assess the compliance

    costs they would impose on businesses. That body, later called the Deregula-

    tion Unit and housed in the Cabinet Ofce, had, by 1996, started to subject

    regulations to a newly taxing process of regulatory appraisal,17 but the high

    point of deregulatory action had come with the passing of the Deregulation

    and Contracting Out Act 1994 which inter alia had given ministers the power

    to use secondary legislative to eliminate burdens and controls. No rigorous

    16 See J. Kay, C. Mayer, and D. Thompson (eds), Privatisation and Regulation: The UK Experience

    (Oxford, 1986); D. Swann, The Retreat of the State: Deregulation and Privatisation in the UK and US

    (Brighton, 1988); K. Button and D. Swann (eds), The Age of Regulatory Reform (Oxford, 1989); also see

    the White Papers: Building Business, Not Barriers, Cmnd. 9794 (London, 1986); Lifting the Burden,

    Cmnd. 9751 (London, 1985); Releasing Enterprise, Cmnd. 512 (London, 1988); Department of Trade

    and Industry, Burdens on Business (London, 1985); Cabinet Ofce, Checking the Cost of Regulation

    (London, 1996); Regulation in the Balance (London, 1996); M. Derthick and P. Quirk, The Politics of

    Deregulation (Washington, 1985); V. Wright, Public Administration, Regulation, Deregulation and

    Reregulation, in E. Eliassen and J. Kooiman (eds), Managing Public Organisations: Lessons from

    Contemporary European Experience (London, 1993).17 See Regulation in the Balance and Chapter 15 below. Under Labour, the Deregulation Unit was

    renamed the Better Regulation Unit in 1997. In 2006, these functions were split into two: the Better

    Regulation Executive (supporting government departments) and the Better Regulation Commission(tasked with overseeing the implementation of initiatives). In 2008, the Better Regulation Commission

    was replaced by the Risk and Regulation Advisory Council (which in itself ended its activities in 2009).

    The core of regulatory reform initiatives moved to the then Department of Business, Enterprise and

    Regulatory Reform (BERR). At the time of writing (2011), the Better Regulation Executive remained

    located within the (now called) Department of Business, Innovation and Skills.

    INTRODUCTION 5

  • review of the impact of such initiatives was, however, carried out by the Major

    government and promises of bonres of red tape were not fullled.

    It was in the eld of utilities regulation that the most urgent political

    debates took place towards the end of the last millennium.18 Attention

    focused on the issues of efciency, accountability, and fairness in the system

    of regulating by means of Directors General and their accompanying ofces.

    A host of books and reports emerged from all parts of the political spectrum

    to put forward a large number of reform proposals.19 These were accompan-

    ied by signicant contributions, many of which originated to the practice of

    economic regulation of utilities, in industrial economics.20

    In parallel to these developments in the regulation of economic and

    social activities, there was also the rise of regulation inside government. This

    included a growing prominence of formal auditing and nancial controlling

    activities, the emergence of oversight mechanisms that sought to check on the

    quality or effectiveness of public services, such as prisons, schools, hospitals,

    and universities, as well as the growing codication of ethics provisions

    supposedly guiding public ofcials. All of these processes had been regulated

    in one way or another, but, despite considerable variations across domains,

    the regulation industry inside UK government witnessed a considerable

    growth at a time of wider reductions in public service staff numbers

    elsewhere.21

    By the turn of the millennium, the appropriateness of regulatory strategies

    and structures had become a signicant public concern, and this led to a set of

    responses and debates over the rst decade following 2000.22

    18 For a review of this debate see R. Baldwin, Regulation in Question (London, 1995).19 See e.g. C. Veljanovski, The Future of Industry Regulation in the UK (London, 1993); Adam Smith

    Institute,Who Will Regulate the Regulators? (London, 1992); P. Hain, Regulating for the Common Good

    (London, 1994); Centre for the Study of Regulated Industries, Regulating the Utilities: Accountability

    and Processes (London, 1994); National Consumer Council, Paying the Price (London, 1993);

    C. Graham, Is There a Crisis in Regulatory Accountability? (London, 1995 and reproduced in Baldwin,

    Scott, and Hood, Regulation); D. Helm, British Utilities Regulation (Oxford, 1995); M.E. Beesley (ed.),

    Regulatory Utilities: A Time for Change? (London, 1996); Regulating Utilities: Broadening the Debate

    (London, 1997); DTI Green Paper, A Fair Deal for Consumers: Modernising the Framework for Utility

    Regulation, Cmnd 3898 (March, 1998).20 J. Vickers and G. Yarrow, Privatisation: An Economic Analysis (Cambridge, MA, 1988);

    M. Armstrong, S. Cowan, and J. Vickers, Regulatory Reform: Economic Analysis and British Experience

    (Cambridge, MA, 1994); D. Newbery, Privatization, Restructuring and Regulation of Network Utilities

    (Cambridge, MA, 1999).21 C. Hood, C. Scott, O. James, G. Jones, and T. Travers (eds), Regulation Inside Government

    (Oxford, 1999); C. Hood, O. James, G.B. Peters, and C. Scott (eds), Controlling Modern Government

    (Cheltenham, 2004); M. Lodge and C. Hood, Regulation Inside Government: Retro-Theory Vindi-cated or Outdated? in R. Baldwin, M. Cave, and M. Lodge (eds), Oxford Handbook of Regulation

    (Oxford, 2010).22 M. Lodge, Regulation, the Regulatory State and European Politics (2008) 30 (1/2) West

    European Politics 280301; T. Prosser, The Regulatory Enterprise (Oxford, 2010); D. Oliver, T. Prosser,

    and R. Rawlings (eds), The Regulatory State: Constitutional Implications (Oxford, 2010).

    6 INTRODUCTION

  • One prominent issue was the governance of regulatory bodies. In the

    British context, debates on this matter led not just to a merger of regulatory

    bodies in energy and communications, they also produced a change in the

    leadership structure, with the original, and initially much-feted Director

    General-model being replaced by collective decision-making boards. Indeed,

    the widely reported collapse of the privatized railway infrastructure provider,

    Railtrack, and its transfer into a non-dividend paying public company, as

    well as the associated fall-out between ministers and the then regulator,

    conrmed arguements that the regulatory reforms of the 1980s and 1990s

    were far from achieving depoliticized stability: instead, the world of regula-

    tion continued to be one of high politics.23

    A second concern related to the effects and biases of regulatory regimes. In

    particular, there was a growing worry about investments in infrastructures

    and the environmental effects of regulated industries, especially with regard to

    climate change.24

    A third debate that grew in the new millennium was one driven by the

    emergence of new technologies and products. New products have come to

    market with increasing speed in recent times and consumers preferences have

    shifted, especially as consumers have become increasingly critical of the food

    production chain in the light of a series of food safety scandals, starting with

    so-called Mad Cow Disease. The arrival of genetically modied (GM) food

    and the new communications technologies, for instance, are two areas that

    have produced rafts of new control challenges and in another areagambling

    via the internetnew technologies have changed the frontiers of existing

    regulatory regimes.25

    With respect to regulatory strategy, the past decade has witnessed a growing

    appetite to explore the potential of non-traditional methods of regulation.

    Commentators have, for instance, devoted new attention to the potential and

    limitations of market-based control strategies such as franchising and permit-

    trading regimes. There has been greater weight given to arguments for

    controlling not by state regulation but by meta-regulation and regimes

    that focus on auditing the control regimes being operated within businesses

    and corporations themselves.26 A further recent change that has emerged in

    23 M. Lodge, The Wrong Type of Regulation? (2002) 22(3) Journal of Public Policy 27197.24 D. Helm, The New Regulatory Agenda (London, 2004). For example, the UK government

    published proposals to reform energy regulation in late 2010 that was supposed to incentivize low-

    carbon forms of energy generation; see Nuclear option poised to test coalition further, Financial

    Times, 17 Dec. 2010.25 For a comparison between high and low tech policy domains and regulatory responses, see

    J. Black, M. Lodge, and M. Thatcher (eds), Regulatory Innovation (Cheltenham, 2005).26 J. Braithwaite, Meta Risk Management and Responsive Regulation for Tax System Integrity

    (2003) 25 Law and Policy 116; C. Coglianese and D. Lazer, Management Based Regulation: Prescrib-

    ing Private Management to Achieve Public Goals (2003) 37 Law and Society Review 691730; P. May,

    Performance-Based Regulation and Regulatory Regimes: the Saga of Leaky Buildings (2003) 25 Law

    INTRODUCTION 7

  • parallel with such auditing approaches has been the growth of a tendency to

    see regulatory issues in terms of risks and to see control issues as questions of

    risk management.27 At the same time, governmental bodies have echoed these

    approaches, and bodies such as the UKs (then) Better Regulation Task Force

    have commended the use of more imaginative thinking about regulation and

    have stressed the need to adopt minimalist or self-regulatory controls in the

    rst instance.28 Similar ideas have also come increasingly on to the agenda of

    international bodies, such as the OECD with its high-quality regulation

    initiative and the European Union with its own extensive programme on

    (regulatory) impact assessments. As a result of this international and national

    concern, the better regulation agenda diffused internationally, moving these

    discourses towards emerging economies such as Brazil.29

    Such discussions of meta-regulation and steering raised questions about

    the bodies that should be given the task of regulating and the level of

    government at which regulation should be positioned. Just as calls for

    meta-regulation indicated the interest of some commentators in placing

    the control function within the corporation, others grew more concerned

    about the degree to which regulation operated inside the government itself

    and still others saw the important shift to be towards regulation by supra-

    national bodies (state or private) within a framework of globalization.30

    Another important focal concern has developed in inuence over the last

    decade. A strand of scholarship has emphasized the degree to which regula-

    tory regimes are fragmented, multi-sourced, and unfocused.31 On this view,

    fragmented regulatory authority is frequently encountered within national

    systems, and public, private, and (increasingly) hybrid organizations often

    share regulatory authority. This perspective suggests that to study regulation

    and Policy 381401; C. Parker, Regulator-Required Corporate Compliance Program Audits (2003) 25

    Law and Policy 22144; M. Power, The Audit Society (Oxford, 1997); M. Power,Organized Uncertainty:

    Designing a World of Risk Management (Oxford, 2007).27 J. Black, The Emergence of Risk-based Regulation and the New Public Risk Management in the

    UK, (2005) Public Law 51248; C. Hood, H. Rothstein, and R. Baldwin, The Government of Risk

    (Oxford, 2001). See also H. Rothstein, M. Huber, and G. Gaskell, A Theory of Risk Colonization

    (2006) 35 Economy and Society 91112.28 Better Regulation Task Force, More Imaginative Thinking About Regulation (London, 2003).29 K. Wegrich, Das Leitbild Better Regulation: Ziele, Instrumente, Wirkungsweise (Berlin, 2011);

    M. Lodge and K. Wegrich, High Quality Regulation: Its Popularity, Its Tools and Its Future (2009) 29

    (3) Public Money and Management 14552.30 J. Braithwaite and P. Drahos, Global Business Regulation (Cambridge, 2000); D. Kerwer, Rules

    that Many Use: Standards and Global Regulation (2005) 18 Governance 61132; E. Meidinger,

    Competitive Supra-Governmental Regulation: How Could it be Democratic? Buffalo Legal StudiesResearch Paper Series 2007-007 available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1001770; P. Pattberg, The

    Institutionalization of Private Governance: How Business and Nonprot Organizations Agree on

    Transnational Rules (2005) 18 Governance 589610.31 J. Black, Decentring Regulation: Understanding the Role of Regulation and Self-regulation in a

    Post-Regulatory World (2001) 54 Current Legal Problems 10347.

    8 INTRODUCTION

  • by looking at single regulatory agencies is to adopt rather a limited viewpoint.

    Such decentred interpretations of regulation have also highighted the need

    to take on board the multi-level character of regulation, in which standards

    may be set or agreed at supranational or international levels and enforcement

    may take place in the locality.

    When more specic regulatory questions have been explored, there have

    also been dramatic changes of treatment during the new millennium.

    A regulatory issue that has been particularly productive of fresh theories

    and approaches has been that of enforcement and compliance. Long gone

    are the days when one might comfortably profess to be an advocate of either

    compliance or deterrence approaches. In the wake of the well-established

    theories of responsive regulation32 and smart regulation,33 newer theories of

    problem-centred34 regulation have moved compliance theory onwards, and

    have then been both exposed to criticism and rened. More attention has

    been paid to motivations and behaviours,35 to interactions of control sys-

    tems,36 and to risk-based and principles-based approaches to regulatory

    enforcement.37

    As regulation has come to the forefront of public debates in recent years,

    some particular issues have exerted an especially strong grasp on public and

    political attentionson either a continuing or an ephemeral basis. There has,

    for instance, been a sustained concern about the evils of regulation, such as

    red tape, overload, and the excessive bureaucratization of economic and

    social life. Critics have suggested that regulation creates major barriers to

    competitiveness and economic growth, and such worries have been fuelled by

    benchmarking exercises and league tables such as the World Banks Doing

    Business reports.

    In some cases, particular items have shifted place on the regulation agenda

    so that debates about the virtues and vices of deregulation and privatization

    have, as noted, given way to post-millennium discussions of regulatory

    improvement and better regulation. In these newer conversations about

    regulation, it has become accepted, not only that regulation is necessary for

    the functioning of a market economy, but that regulatory oversight remains

    essential in the running of public services, especially those involving

    32 I. Ayres and J. Braithwaite, Responsive Regulation (Oxford, 1992).33 N. Gunningham and P. Grabosky, Smart Regulation (Oxford, 1998).34 M. Sparrow, The Regulatory Craft (Washington DC, 2000).35 C. Sunstein and R.Thaler, Nudge (New Haven, 2008); C. Jolls, C. Sunstein, and R. Thaler,

    A Behavioural Approach to Law and Economics in C. Sunstein (ed.), Behavioural Law and Economics(Cambridge, 2008).

    36 R. Baldwin and J. Black, Really Responsive Regulation (2008) 71(1)Modern Law Review 5994;

    J. Black and R. Baldwin, Really Responsive Risk-Based Regulation (2010) 32(2) Law and Policy

    181213.37 See Chapters 13 and 14 below.

    INTRODUCTION 9

  • naturally monopolistic elements, such as networks. An initial emphasis on

    economic regulation that was supposed to wither away over time has been

    replaced by a realization that there is a continuing need for regulatory

    oversight and an imperative to add environmental and sustainability objec-

    tives to the earlier, primarily economic and social, objectives.

    These freshly developing agendas of regulation have not, however, always

    gelled into highly coherent packages of policy or theory. The better regulation

    group of initiatives can, for instance, be seen as rich in tensions and contra-

    dictions. Thus, calls have been made for more evidence-based regulation (and

    data-intensive, risk-based regulation) but, at the same time, governments have

    demanded that regulators make fewer informational and data supply demands

    on businesses. Similarly, the past decade or so has seen the spread of rational-

    istic and formal modes of evaluating regulatory proposals (notably Regulatory

    Impact Assessments) and, at the same time, many governments have urged

    regulators to move towards the kinds of regulatory styles that are least likely to

    score convincingly in RIA appraisalssuch as more user-friendly and less

    formal modes of control (see, further, Chapter 15). In itself, the better

    regulation agenda could be seen as an uneasy rhetorical package that com-

    bines a continuation of the anti-red tape message and the belief in techno-

    cratic and rationalizing tools for enhancing regulatory quality.38

    By 2010, regulation had come to occupy a place at the forefront of public

    debate in more than one domain. The nancial crisis that was initially to have

    led to a return of the state pointed to the problems that could be caused by

    an over-reliance on the self-regulatory capacities of private organization.39 It

    also highlighted a series of issues regarding enforcement styles and overall

    regulatory arrangements. By 2011, regulatory debates continued to be domin-

    ated by demands and warnings, on the one side, to impose more regulation

    (in many variants: more rules, tougher sanctions, growing distinctiveness and

    professionalization of regulators) and, on the other, cautioning that more

    regulation would have considerable undesirable effects. The nancial crisis

    also added to global regulation debates on such matters as how systemic risks

    could be coped with across jurisdictions, and how national regulators

    (through the Basel III agreement) could coordinate their macroprudential

    actions and impose capital requirements to cope with overheated national

    economies.40 Environmental disasters, such as the Louisiana oil-spill of 2010,

    brought their own regulatory disputes.41

    38 T.O. McGarity, Reinventing Rationality: The Role of Regulatory Analysis in the Federal Bureaucracy

    (Cambridge, 1991).39 M. Lodge and K. Wegrich, Letter to the Editor, Public Administration Review (2010).40 Bank Regulators Agree on Global Sweep to Tackle Credit Bubbles, Financial Times, 11 Jan. 2011.41 National Commission on the BP Deepwater Horizon Oil Spill and Offshore Drilling (2011),

    Final Report (www.oilspillcommission.gov/nal-report, last accessed 14 January 2011). The National

    Commission on the BP spill criticized the lack of resources allocated to the regulator and called for the

    10 INTRODUCTION

  • As a result of such developments and crises, regulation now occupies its

    place as a central organizing concern for the worlds of practice and research

    alike. At the same time, it has increasingly been asked whether regimes of

    regulation or self-regulation can satisfactorily solve complex problemsand

    not just in the context of the nancial crisis. Advocacy of different regulatory

    strategies has, moreover, tended to proceed on a cautious basis and critiques

    of regulation have tended to emerge in a process of interaction between the

    study and the practice of regulation.

    The Organization of the Book

    Part I of the book reviews a series of general issues in regulation, namely:

    why regulate at all (Chapter 2); how good regulation can be identied

    (Chapter 3); how the origins of regulation and regulatory changes can be

    explained (Chapter 4); and how regulatory failures can be understood

    (Chapter 5). It also considers, in Chapter 6, the challenges of regulating

    risks and the vision of regulation as a risk-centred activity.

    Part II of the book then looks at strategic issues and how regulation can be

    carried out. Central concerns are: choices of regulatory strategy (Chapter 7);

    self-regulatory, meta-regulatory, and complex regimes (Chapter 8); franchis-

    ing (Chapter 9); and emissions trading (Chapter 10). Part III examines enforce-

    ment and implementation matters. It starts with a general review of these issues

    in Chapter 11 before looking at the more particular approaches of responsive

    regulation (Chapter 12); and risk-based regulation (Chapter 13). The problems

    that are encountered in choosing types of regulatory standards are considered

    in Chapter 14, together with the case for principles-based regulation.

    Part IV turns attention to questions of evaluation of the quality of regula-

    tion. Cost-benet testing and Regulatory Impact Assessment are looked at in

    Chapter 15. Accountability and procedural fairness concerns are discussed in

    Chapter 16. Finally, the role and incidence of competition and coordination

    between regulators is addressed in Chapter 17.

    Part V reviews a host of issues that relate to the governmental levels

    at which regulatory systems are located. Chapter 18 deals generally with

    regulation at different levels before Chapter 19 considers the European

    creation of a new safety regulator. The Commission also criticized the prevalence of self-regulation inthe sector, especially the role in which the American Petroleum Institute which produced national

    and global technical standards, was predisposed to rely on industry autonomy. It called for the

    creation of an industry-based safety standard-setting body and enforcinga demand that was widely

    contested, with opponents noting in particular the nancial implications of these proposalssee US

    cannot walk away from oil in deep water, Financial Times, 12 Jan. 2011.

    INTRODUCTION 11

  • dimension to regulation. Development and globalization issues are

    covered by Chapters 20 and 21, respectively. Part VI then looks at utility or

    network industry issues, and focuses on: price setting in natural monopolies

    (Chapter 22); using competition in network industries (Chapter 23); separa-

    tion and contestability in network industries (Chapter 24); implementing

    price controls (Chapter 25); and efciency and innovation in network in-

    dustries (Chapter 26). Conclusions are offered in Chapter 27.

    12 INTRODUCTION

  • Part I

    Fundamentals

  • This page intentionally left blank

  • 2 Why Regulate?

    Motives for regulating can be distinguished from technical justications for

    regulating. Governments may regulate for a number of motivesfor example,

    they may be inuenced by the economically powerful and may act in the

    interests of the regulated industry or they may see a particular regulatory

    stance as a means to re-election. Different commentators may analyse such

    motives in different ways, and a variety of approaches to such analysis will be

    discussed in Chapter 3. To begin, though, we should consider the technical

    justications for regulating that may be given by a government that is assumed

    to be acting in pursuit of the public interest.1

    Many of the rationales for regulating can be described as instances of market

    failure. Regulation in such cases is argued to be justied because the uncon-

    trolled marketplace will, for some reason, fail to produce behaviour or results

    in accordance with the public interest.2 In some sectors or circumstances, there

    may also be market absencethere may be no effective marketbecause, for

    example, households cannot buy clean air or peace and quiet in their localities.

    In this chapter, we discuss the traditional market failure rationales for regulat-

    ing, but we also consider the argument that there may be other reasons to

    regulate and that these have a basis in human rights or social solidarity, rather

    than market, considerations.

    Market Failure Rationales

    MONOPOLIES AND NATURAL MONOPOLIES

    Monopoly describes the position in which one seller produces for the entire

    industry or market. Monopoly pricing and output is likely to occur and be

    sustained where three factors obtain:3

    1 For detailed reviews of public interest reasons for regulating see S. Breyer, Regulation and ItsReform (Cambridge, MA, 1982), ch. 1; A. Ogus, Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory (Oxford,

    1994), ch. 3; E. Gellhorn and R.J. Pierce, Regulated Industries (St Paul, MN, 1982), ch. 2; J. Kay and

    J. Vickers, Regulatory Reform: An Appraisal, in G. Majone (ed.), De-Regulation or Re-Regulation?

    (London, 1989); B. Mitnick, The Political Economy of Regulation (New York, 1980), ch. 5; C. Sunstein,

    After the Rights Revolution (Cambridge, MA, 1990), ch. 2; C. Hood, Explaining Economic Policy

    Reversals (Buckingham, 1995).2 See also J. Francis, The Politics of Regulation (Oxford, 1993), ch. 1.3 See Gellhorn and Pierce, Regulated Industries, 367 and Chapter 15 below. On regulating

    monopolies generally see C. Foster, Privatisation, Public Ownership and the Regulation of Natural

    Monopoly (Oxford, 1992), ch. 6; Ogus, Regulation, 303; Breyer, Regulation and Its Reform, 1519;

  • A single seller occupies the entire market. The product sold is unique in the sense that there is no substitute suf-

    ciently close for consumers to turn to.

    Substantial barriers restrict entry by other rms into the industry, and exitis difcult.

    Where monopoly occurs, the market fails because competition is decient.

    From the public interest perspective, the problem with a rm occupying a

    monopolistic position is that in maximizing prots it will restrict its output

    and set price above marginal cost. It will do this because if it charges a single

    price for its product, additional sales will only be achieved by lowering the

    price on the entire output. The monopolist will forgo sales to the extent that

    lost revenue from fewer sales will be compensated for by higher revenue

    derived from increased price on the units still sold. The effects of monopoly,

    as compared to perfect competition, are reduced output, higher prices, and

    transfer of income from consumers to producers.

    One response to potential monopolies is to use competition (or antitrust)

    laws so as to create a business environment that is conducive to competition.

    Where a natural monopoly exists, however, the use of competition law may

    be undesirable.4 A natural monopoly occurs when economies of scale avail-

    able in the production process are so large that the relevant market can be

    served at the least cost by a single rm. It is accordingly less costly to society

    to have production carried out by one rm than by many. Thus, rather than

    have three railway or electricity companies laying separate networks of rails

    or cables where one would do, it may be more efcient to give one rm a

    monopoly subject to regulation of such matters as prices and access to the

    network. Determining whether a natural monopoly exists requires a compari-

    son of demand for the product with the extent of the economies of scale

    available in production. If a rm is in a position of natural monopoly then,

    like any monopoly, it will present problems of reduced output, higher prices,

    and transfers of wealth from consumers to the rm. Restoration of competi-

    tion by use of competition law is not, however, an appropriate response, since

    competition may be socially costly and thus regulation of prices, quality, and

    output as well as access may be called for. The regulator will try to set price

    near incremental cost (the cost of producing an additional unit) in order to

    encourage the natural monopolist to expand its output to the level that

    competitive conditions would have induced.

    Francis, Politics of Regulation, ch. 3; E. Gellhorn andW. Kovacic, Antitrust Law and Economics (St Paul,

    Minn., 1994), chs. 3 and 4.4 On natural monopolies see M. Waterson, Regulation of the Firm and Natural Monopoly (Oxford,

    1988), ch. 2; Foster, Privatisation, ch. 6.2.

    16 FUNDAMENTALS

  • Not all aspects of a supply process may be naturally monopolistic. As Ogus

    points out,5 the economies of scale phenomenon may affect only one part of

    a given processfor instance the transmission of, say, electricity, rather than

    its generation.6 The task of many governments and regulators (at least those

    committed to minimalist regulation) is to identify those parts of a process

    that are naturally monopolistic so that these can be regulated while other

    aspects are left to the inuence of competitive forces.7

    WINDFALL PROFITS

    A rm will earn a windfall prot (sometimes called an economic rent

    or excess prot) where it nds a source of supply signicantly cheaper

    than that available in the marketplace.8 It may do so by, say, locating

    a rich seam of an easily extracted mineral; by coming upon a material

    efciency in a production process; or by possessing an asset that sud-

    denly escalates in valuefor example, a boat in a desert town that has been

    ooded. Regulation may be called for when it is desired either to transfer

    prots to taxpayers or to allow consumers or the public to benet from the

    windfall.

    Where the windfall is the result of planned investments of money, effort, or

    research, or where society might want to create incentives to search for new

    efciencies, products, or areas of demand, there is a case for allowing windfall

    prots to be retained. (If excess prots are earned, it may be appropriate to

    limit these so that rewards and incentives are proportionate to the effort or

    investment that has produced the return.) In the desert town, it may be

    desirable to encourage some individuals to store boats in order to cope with

    periodic oods. If, however, the windfall is the result of good fortune rather

    than effort, exploration, or research, the case for taking the prots for public

    benet may be stronger. Even in such cases, however, there will still be

    an argument for leaving windfall prots where they lie. If the state deprives

    a property owner of the windfalls that ow from such ownership, this may be

    seen by market actors as rendering property rights less secure, and this

    uncertainty may be bad for business generally. The balance between the

    publics gains from intervention and any negative effects on markets will

    have to be assessed in specic cases.

    5 Ogus, Regulation, 31.6 G. Yarrow, Regulation and Competition in the Electricity Supply Industry, in J. Kay, C. Mayer,

    and D. Thompson (eds), Privatisation and Regulation (Oxford, 1986).7 See Chapter 23 below, and the White Paper, Privatising Electricity, Cmnd. 322 (London, 1988).8 See Breyer, Regulation and Its Reform, 21.

    WHY REGULATE? 17

  • EXTERNALITIES

    The reason for regulating externalities (or spillovers) is that the price of a

    product does not reect the true cost to society of producing that good, and

    excessive consumption accordingly results.9 Thus, a manufacturer of car tyres

    might keep costs to consumers down by dumping pollutants arising from the

    manufacturing process into a river. The price of the tyres will not represent

    the true costs that production imposes on society if clean-up costs are left out

    of account. The resultant process is wasteful because too many resources are

    attracted into polluting activities (too many tyres are made and sold) and too

    few resources are devoted by the manufacturer to pollution avoidance or

    adopting pollution-free production methods. The rationale for regulation is

    to eliminate this wasteand to protect society or third parties suffering

    from externalitiesby compelling the internalization of spillover costson

    polluter pays principles.

    INFORMATION INADEQUACIES

    Competitive markets can only function properly if consumers are suf-

    ciently well informed to evaluate competing products.10 The market may,

    however, fail to produce adequate information and may fail for a number of

    reasons: information may cost money to produce (e.g. because researching

    the effects of a product, such as a drug, may prove expensive). The producer

    of information, however, may not be compensated by others who use that

    information (e.g. other manufacturers of the drug). The incentive to pro-

    duce information may accordingly be low. There may also be incentives to

    falsify informationwhere, for example, consumers of the product are ill-

    positioned to challenge the falsication and seek remedies for damages

    suffered or where they face high costs in doing so. Areas in which consumers

    purchase a type of product very infrequently may give rise to this problem.

    The information produced may, in addition, not be of sufcient assistance

    to the consumerfor instance, because the consumer lacks the expertise

    required to render technical data useful. Finally, collusion in the market-

    place, or insufcient competition, may reduce the ow of information below

    the levels consumers might want. Producers, as a group, may thus fail to

    warn consumers about the general hazards or deciencies associated with a

    product. Breyer notes that until the US government required disclosure,

    accurate information was unavailable to most buyers in that country

    9 See Breyer, Regulation and Its Reform, 236; Ogus, Regulation, 358.10 See F. Hayek, The Use of Knowledge in Society (1945) 35 American Economic Review 519;

    Breyer, Regulation and Its Reform, 268; Ogus, Regulation, 3841.

    18 FUNDAMENTALS

  • concerning the durability of light bulbs, nicotine content of cigarettes, fuel

    economy for cars, or care requirements for textiles.11

    Regulation, by making information more extensively accessible, accurate,

    and affordable, may protect consumers against information inadequacies

    and the consequences thereof, and may encourage the operation of healthy,

    competitive markets.

    CONTINUITY AND AVAILABILITY OF SERVICE

    In some circumstances, the market may not provide the socially desired levels

    of continuity and availability of service. Thus, where demand is cyclical (for

    example, as with passenger air transport to a holiday island)wastemayoccur as

    rms go through the processes of closing and reopening operations.12 Regula-

    tion may be used to sustain services through troughsfor example, by setting

    minimum prices at levels allowing the covering of xed costs through lean

    periods. Thiswould be justiedwhere the extra costs imposed on consumers by

    pricing rules are less than those caused by the processes of closing and opening

    services in response to the business cycle. The subsidizing of off-peak by peak

    travellers will, however, raise issues of equity to be considered alongside ques-

    tions of social policy. In the case of some products or servicesfor example,

    water servicesit may be considered, as a matter of social policy, that these

    should be generally available at least to a certain minimum standard. In the

    unregulated market, however, competition may lead to cream-skimming

    the process in which the producer chooses to supply only the most protable

    customersand services may be withdrawn from poorer or more geographi-

    cally dispersed groupings of customers. Regulationmay be justied in order to

    produce socially desirable results, even though the cross-subsidizations ef-

    fected may be criticizable as inefcient and unfair.

    ANTI-COMPETITIVE BEHAVIOUR AND PREDATORY PRICING

    Markets may be decient not merely because competition is lacking: they may

    produce undesirable effects because rms behave in a manner not conducive

    to healthy competition. A principal manifestation of such behaviour is pred-

    atory pricing. This occurs when a rm prices below costs, in the hope of

    driving competitors from the market, achieving a degree of domination, and

    then using its position to recover the costs of predation and increase prots at

    the expense of consumers. Preconditions for a rational rm to engage in

    predatory pricing are that: it must be able to outlast its competitors once

    prices are cut below variable costs; and it must be able to maintain prices well

    11 Breyer, Regulation and Its Reform, 28. 12 Ogus, Regulation, 436.

    WHY REGULATE? 19

  • above costs for long enough to recover its prior losses. The costs of entry to

    and exit from the market must, accordingly, allow it this period of comfort

    before new competition arises. The aim for regulators is to sustain competi-

    tion and protect consumers from the ill-effects of market domination by

    outlawing predatory or other forms of anti-competitive behaviour.

    PUBLIC GOODS AND MORAL HAZARD

    Some commodities, e.g. security and defence services, may bring shared

    benets and be generally desired. It may, however, be very costly for those

    paying for such services to prevent non-payers (free-riders) from enjoying

    the benets of those services. As a result, the market may fail to encourage the

    production of such commodities, and regulation may be requiredoften to

    overcome the free-rider problem by imposing taxes.

    Similarly, where there is an instance of moral hazardwhere someone

    other than the consumer pays for a service13there may be excessive con-

    sumption without regard to the resource costs being imposed on society.

    If, for example, medical costs are not met by the patient, but by the state or

    an insurer, regulatory constraints may be required if excessive consumption of

    medical services is to be avoided.

    UNEQUAL BARGAINING POWER

    One precondition for the efcient or fair allocation of resources in a market is

    equal bargaining power. If bargaining power is unequal, regulation may be

    justied in order to protect certain interests. Thus, if unemployment is

    prevalent it cannot be assumed that workers will be able to negotiate effec-

    tively to protect their interests, and regulation may be required to safeguard

    such matters as the health and safety of those workers. Inequalities of bargain-

    ing power may thus be the products of relative positions in the marketplace,

    but they may also stem from asymmetries of information. Workers, for

    instance, may be poorly placed to secure health protections from their

    employers because they lack the information that would put them on an

    equal footing in negotiations.

    SCARCITY AND RATIONING

    Regulatory rather than market mechanisms may be justied in order to

    allocate certain commodities when these are in short supply. In a petrol

    13 See generally G. Calabresi, The Cost of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis (New

    Haven, 1970).

    20 FUNDAMENTALS

  • shortage, for example, public interest objectives may take precedence over

    efciency so that, instead of using pricing as an allocative instrument,

    the petrol is allocated with reference to democratically generated lists of

    priorities.

    RATIONALIZATION AND COORDINATION

    In many situations, it is extremely expensive for individuals to negotiate

    private contracts so as to organize behaviour or industries in an efcient

    mannerthe transaction costs would be excessive.14 The rms in an industry

    may be too small and geographically dispersed to bring themselves together to

    produce efciently. (This might happen when small shing concerns in a

    sparsely populated area fail to make collective marketing arrangements.)

    Enterprises may, moreover, have developed different and incompatible

    modes of production. In these circumstances, regulation may be justied as

    a means of rationalizing production processes (perhaps standardizing equip-

    ment in order to create effective networks) and in order to coordinate the

    market. Centralized regulation holds the advantage over individual private

    law arrangements, where information can be more efciently communicated

    through public channels and economies of scale can be achieved by having

    one public agency responsible for upholding standards.15

    It is noteworthy that this rationale for regulation is based more on the

    desire to enable effective action to take place than on the need to prohibit

    undesirable behaviour.

    PLANNING

    Markets may ensure reasonably well that individuals consumer preferences

    are met, but they are less able to meet the demands of future generations or to

    satisfy altruistic concerns (e.g. the quality of an environment not personally

    enjoyed).16 There is also, as far as altruism is concerned, a potential free-rider

    problem. Many people may be prepared to give up some of their assets for

    altruistic purposes only if they can be assured that a large number of others

    14 See Ogus, Regulation, 412; S. Breyer and P. MacAvoy, The Federal Power Commission and the

    Coordination Problem in the Electrical Power Industry (1973) 46 Southern California Law

    Review 661.15 In the transportation sector, coordination and regulation by a central agency may be needed in

    order to organize a route networksee S. Glaister, Deregulation and Privatisation: British Experience

    (Washington, DC, 1998).16 See Ogus, Regulation, 54; R.B. Stewart, Regulation in a Liberal State: The Role of Non-

    Commodity Values (1983) 92 Yale Law Journal 1537; Sunstein, After the Rights Revolution, 5761.

    WHY REGULATE? 21

  • will do the same. The problems and costs of coordination mean that regula-

    tion may be required in order to satisfy such desires.17

    Rights-based and Social Rationales for Regulating

    It has been argued, notably by Tony Prosser,18 that the market failure rationale

    does not adequately justify the range of regulatory activities that are com-

    monly undertaken. He suggests, moreover, that the market failure analysis

    treats regulation as second-best to market allocation and that this does not

    properly explain or justify current practice. Prosser, accordingly, points to the

    relevance of two further rationales for regulatingto protect human rights19

    and to further social solidarity.20 In doing so, he takes issue with the assump-

    tions that market solutions are always the best ways to deal with decisions on

    the allocation of goods and services, and that non-market failure rationales

    for regulating are essentially arbitrary. The idea that market allocations are

    technical whereas social justice issues are political is also questioned. What

    can be said as a matter of description, says Prosser, is that environmental and

    many other regulators can properly be seen as seeking to further social

    objectives, rather than as simply acting to correct market failures. Even

    where markets are involved, regulatory laws, on such a view, are not limited

    to merely correcting the market but often serve to constitute market relations,

    to provide the frameworks of rights and processes that allow markets to work,

    and to protect markets from fragmentation. In many contexts, accordingly,

    regulation can be seen as prior, not secondary, to the market and as a rst-

    choice method of organizing social relations.21

    17 Ogus, Regulation, 54.18 T. Prosser, Regulation and Social Solidarity (2006) 33 Journal of Law and Society 36487; Public

    Service Law (2000) 63 Law and Contemporary Problems 6382. See also C. McCrudden, Social Policy

    and Economic Regulators in C. McCrudden, Regulation and Deregulation (Oxford, 1999) and M.

    Feintuck, Regulatory Rationales Beyond the Economic in R. Baldwin, M. Cave and M. Lodge (eds),

    The Oxford Handbook of Regulation (Oxford, 2010).19 See R. Brownsword, What the World Needs Now: Techno-Regulation, Human Rights and

    Human Dignity in R. Brownsword (ed.), Global Governance and the Quest for Justice (Oxford, 2004).20 A developing of the argument is offered in T. Prosser, The Regulatory Enterprise: Government

    Regulation and Legitimacy (Oxford, 2010), 1120, where four rationales for regulation are distin-

    guished: (1) regulation for economic efciency and consumer choice (market-centred regulation);

    (2) regulation to protect rights; (3) regulation for social solidarity; and (4) regulation as deliberation

    (the provision of processes to resolve problems). See also H. McVea, Financial Services RegulationUnder the Financial Services Authority: A Reassertion of the Market Failure Thesis? (2005) 64

    Cambridge Law Journal 41348; J. Black, Critical Reections on Regulation, LSE Centre for Analysis

    of Risk and Regulation (CARR), Discussion Paper 4 (2002).21 See C. Shearing, A Constitutive Conception of Regulation in P. Grabosky and J. Braithwaite

    (eds), Business Regulation and Australias Future (Canberra, 1994).

    22 FUNDAMENTALS

  • Consistent with such regulatory rationales are examples of regulating for

    reasons of distributional justice, rights protection, and citizenshipas, for

    example, where regulated utilities are obliged to apply geographically aver-

    aged tariffs or to meet universal service obligations. Governments, indeed,

    regulate on a host of matters simply in order to further social policies such as

    the prevention of discrimination based on race, sex, or age. Social objectives,

    moreover, are sometimes furthered by regulating even where this involves

    overruling the preferences of market players and acting paternalistically. Thus,

    society may, as a matter of policy, decide to act in the face of drivers desires

    and demand that seat belts be worn in motor vehicles. In the strongest form of

    such paternalism, the decision is taken to regulate even where it is accepted

    that the citizens involved would not support regulation and that they are

    possessed of full information on the relevant issue.22

    Conclusions: Choosing to Regulate

    There are, as seen above (and in Table 2.1) a number of well-recognized

    reasons commonly given for regulating. It should be stressed, however, that in

    any one sector or industry the case for regulating may well be based not on a

    single but on a combination of rationalesbe these market failure-, human

    rights-, or social solidarity-based. Health and safety regulation, for example,

    can be justied with reference to such matters as externalities, information

    defects, unequal bargaining, human rights, and paternalism.23

    A second point to be borne in mind in considering whether to regulate,

    is that the market and all its failings should be compared with regulation

    and all its failings. Any analysis of the need to regulate will be skewed if it is

    assumed that regulatory techniques will operate perfectly. We will see during

    this book that all regulatory strategies have strengths and weaknesses

    in relation to their implementation, as well as their design. Regulatory and

    market solutions to problems should be considered in all their varieties

    and with all likely deciencies and side-effects if true comparisons are to

    be effected.

    22 Ibid., 514.23 Breyer, Regulation and Its Reform, 34; Prosser, Regulation and Social Solidarity.

    WHY REGULATE? 23

  • Table 2.1. Rationales for regulating

    Rationale Main aims of regulation Example

    Monopolies and natural

    monpolies

    Counter tendency to raise prices and lower output. Utilities.

    Harness benets of scale economies.

    Identify areas that are genuinely monopolistic.

    Windfall prots Transfer benets of windfalls from rms to consumers

    or taxpayers.

    Firm discovers unusually

    cheap source of supply.

    Externalities Compel producer or consumer to bear full costs of

    production, rather than pass on to third parties or

    society.

    Pollution of river by

    factory.

    Information

    inadequacies

    Inform consumers to allow market to operate. Pharmaceuticals. Food

    and drinks labelling.

    Continuity and

    availability of service

    Ensure socially desired (or protect minimal) level of

    essential service.

    Transport service to

    remote region.

    Anti-competitive and

    predatory pricing

    behaviour

    Prevent anti-competitive behaviour. Below-cost pricing in

    transport.

    Public goods and moral

    hazard

    Share costs where benets of activity are shared but

    free-rider problems exist.

    Defence and security

    services. Health

    Services.

    Unequal bargaining

    power

    Protect vulnerable interests where market fails to do

    so.

    Health and Safety at

    Work.

    Scarcity and rationing Public interest allocation of scarce commodities. Petrol shortage.

    Rationalization and

    coordination

    Secure efcient production where transaction costs

    prevent market from obtaining network gains or

    efciencies of scale.

    Disparate production in

    agriculture and

    sheries.

    Standardization.

    Planning Protect interests of future generations. Environment.

    Coordinate altruistic intentions.

    Human rights Protection of weaker citizens. Discrimination.

    Embryology.

    Social protection Social solidarity. Broadcasting.

    24 FUNDAMENTALS

  • 3 What is Good Regulation?

    To decide whether a system of regulation is good, acceptable, or in need of

    reform it is necessary to be clear about the benchmarks that are relevant in

    such an evaluation.1

    A temptation for some economists may be to assert that regulation is good

    if it is efcient in the sense that it maximizes wealth.2 It can be objected,

    however, that wealth maximization provides no ethical basis for action, that it

    cannot justify any particular distribution of rights within society, and that, as

    a result, it cannot be used to measure regulatory decisions affecting rights.3

    This is because there is circularity in the assertion that one should distrib-

    ute rights (e.g. to pollute or to be free from pollution) in a manner that

    maximizes wealth. For every particular, given, distribution of wealth, there is

    a specic allocation of further rights that will maximize wealththus, how

    best to allocate the new supply of petrol would be governed by who owns

    the machinery that burns petrol.4 Deciding distributional issues on the basis

    of wealth maximization, accordingly, assumes a given distribution from

    the start. Similarly, it is circular to state that rights should be allocated to

    those who value them mostvaluation itself depends on assumptions about

    1 See generally, R. Baldwin and C. McCrudden, Regulation and Public Law (London, 1987), ch. 3;

    R. Baldwin, Rules and Government (Oxford, 1995), ch. 3; J.O. Freedman, Crisis and Legitimacy

    (Cambridge, 1978); C. Radaelli and F. De Francesco, Regulatory Quality in Europe (Manchester,

    2007); J. Stern, The Evaluation of Regulatory Agencies in R. Baldwin, M. Cave, and M. Lodge

    (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Regulation (Oxford, 2010).2 See R.A. Posner, Utilitarianism, Economics and Legal Theory (1979) 8 Journal of. Legal Studies

    103; id., Wealth Maximisation Revisited (1985) 2 Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public

    Policy 85.3 See R. Dworkin, Is Wealth a Value? (1980) 9 Journal of Legal Studies 191; id., Why Efciency

    (1980) 8Hofstra Law Review 563; id., AMatter of Principle (Cambridge, MA, 1986), ch. 13; S. Kelman,

    Cost-Benet Analysis: An Ethical Critique (1981) 5(1) Regulation 33; A. Kronman, Wealth Max-

    imisation as a Normative Principle (1980) 9 Journal of Legal Studies 227; C.G. Veljanovski, Wealth

    Maximisation, Law and Ethics: On the Limits of Economic Efciency (1981) 1 International Review of

    Law and Economics 5; E.J. Weinrib, Utilitarianism, Economics and Legal Theory (1980) 30 University

    of Toronto LJ 307; C. Fried, Difculties in the Economic Analysis of Rights, in G. Dworkin,

    G. Bermont, and P. Brown (eds.), Markets and Morals (Washington, 1977). For a review of the

    literature see N. Duxbury, Patterns of American Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1995), 4006.4 This statement assumes that there are transaction costs. If there are no transaction costs and

    parties can bargain in a friction-free manner then, as the Coase Theorem tells us, any distribution ofrights will maximize wealth and the owners of petrol-burning machines will end up using the petrol

    even if it is not allocated to them in the rst instance. This implies, again, that wealth maximization

    offers no help at all in deciding how to allocate rights. See R. Coase, The Problem of Social Cost

    (1960) 3 Journal of Law and Economics 1; Veljanovski, Wealth Maximisation, 5; and L.A. Bebchuck,

    The Pursuit of a Bigger Pie: Can Everyone Expect a Bigger Slice? (1980) 8 Hofstra Law Review 671.

    CitlaliResaltado

  • the allocation of rights (one can only value if one has something to value

    with or else the valuation takes place in the realms of fantasy). Questions of

    justice, it follows, cannot be answered by economists appeals to efciency

    and distributional questions such as whether it is right to allow an extra

    unit of pollution (thus shifting the balance of rights from, say, river user A to

    polluting factory owner B) have to be made on the basis of grounds other

    than efciency.5

    This is not to say that efciency may not be a factor to be taken into

    account in making regulatory judgements.6 Wemay want to take on board the

    wealth implications of particular distributional choices when deciding, say,

    how to allocate rights between polluters and potential victims. What we

    should be wary of is using efciency as a single measuring rod or justication

    for regulatory decisions. This will involve either circularity, as noted, or the

    assumption that the present distribution of wealth, together with a bias in

    favour of those with wealth, is acceptable.7

    A further moral objection to wealth maximization relates to its implication

    that it is right to allow B to interfere with As rights (e.g. by polluting their

    river or exposing them to a hazardous substance) if B generates enough

    wealth to compensate A for the harm done. Human beings, the objection

    runs, have certain basic rights that it would be morally objectionable to put up

    for sale. Certain risks, it might similarly be said, should not be imposed on

    individuals lives no matter what the price, compensation, or wealth gain

    on offer.8

    Five Criteria for Good Regulation

    More plausible than wealth maximization is an approach to regulatory

    evaluation that involves looking at those arguments that have general cur-

    rency when regulatory arrangements and performance are discussed in the

    public domain. Certain arguments have force in debating whether this or that

    5 For a statement of non-economic substantive goals that would justify regulation according to a

    civic republican viewpoint see C. Sunstein, After the Rights Revolution: Reconceiving the Regulatory

    State (Cambridge MA, 1990).6 On economists contributions see R. Cooter and T. Ulen, Law and Economics (Glenview, IL,

    1988), ch. 1 and see Chapter 15, below, on the cost-benet testing of regulation.7 Those possessing wealth will gain in efciency-based decisions because they value rights more

    highly and are better placed than poorer persons to generate further wealth from the rights at issue: seeC.E. Baker, The Ideology of the Economic Analysis of Law (1975) 5 Philosophy and Public Affairs 3;

    G. Minda, Towards a More Just Economics of JusticeA Review Essay (1989) 10 Cardozo Law

    Review 1855.8 For governmental acknowledgement of this point see HM Treasury, The Setting of Safety

    Standards (London, 1996), 9.

    26 FUNDAMENTALS

    CitlaliResaltado

  • regulatory action or regime is worthy of support (is legitimate).9 These

    arguments involve reference to one or more of ve key tests:

    Is the action or regime supported by legislative authority? Is there an appropriate scheme of accountability? Are procedures fair, accessible, and open? Is the regulator acting with sufcient expertise? Is the action or regime efcient?The ve tests, or criteria, should be explained before their role in assessing

    regulation is discussed further.

    THE LEGISLATIVE MANDATE

    This criterion suggests that regulatory action deserves support when it is

    authorized by Parliament, the fountain of democratic authority. If the people,

    through Parliament, have instructed certain regulators to achieve result X,

    and those regulators can point to their having produced result X, then they

    are in a position to claim public support. They have fullled their mandate.10

    It might be very proper to judge regulators according to their success

    in fullling their mandates. Unfortunately, however, it is seldom easy to

    state in precise terms what this should involve. Most regulatory statutes give

    regulators broad discretions and implementing the mandate thus involves

    interpretation.11 A statute, for example, may order a regulator to protect the

    9 For governmental statements on the criteria for good regulation see Better Regulation Task Force

    (BRTF), Principles of Good Regulation (London, 2003). The principles are: Proportionality, Account-

    ability, Consistency, Transparency, and Targeting; Department of the Taoiseach, Regulating Better

    (Dublin, 2004), www.betterregulation.ie (looking to necessity, effectiveness, proportionality, transpar-

    ency, accountability, and consistency). See also the Australian government, Department of Industry,

    Tourism and Resources: Regulatory Performance Indicators (Canberra, 1999); S. Argy and M. Johnson,

    Mechanisms for Improving the Quality of Regulations: Australian Productivity Commission (Staff

    Working Paper, July 2003). For Canada, see Treasury Board of Canada Secretariat, Federal Regulatory

    Process Management Standards (Ottawa, 1996). The World Bank view is set down in World Bank,

    Doing Business in 2004: Understanding Regulation (Washington, DC, and Oxford, 2004). See also

    OECD, Guiding Principles for Regulatory Quality and Performance (Paris, 2005). For other denitions

    of good or better regulation see Mandelkern Group on Better Regulation, Final Report (Brussels, 13

    Nov. 2002) (Mandelkern Report).10 If Parliament is yet to provide amandate because no regulatory statute has been passed in an area

    say, when a regulatory Bill is being debatedany discussion of good regulation ismore open-ended than

    usual. Reference, in such circumstances, is likely to be made to the four criteria other than the mandate

    that are discussed here and also to governmental claims to possess a mandate for a certain regulatory

    approach (based, for instance, on manifesto statements) and to more general arguments concerningsocial justice. See, for example, the Better Regulation Task Forces 2003 statement that good regulation

    should be: Proportionate, Accountable, Consistent, Transparent, and Targeted (Better Regulation Task

    Force, Principles of Good Regulation (London, 2003).11 See K.C. Davis, Discretionary Justice (Chicago, 1969), 39 and on British utilities see T. Prosser,

    Law and the Regulators (Oxford, 1997), 1531. Lowi suggested that many US regulatory statutes were

    WHAT IS GOOD REGULATION? 27

    CitlaliResaltado

    CitlaliResaltado

    CitlaliResaltado

    CitlaliResaltado

  • interests of consumers, but it may be silent on the balance to be drawn

    between industrial and domestic or large and small consumers interests.

    Such statutes, moreover, often set out objectives that exist at mutual

    tension. Achieving certain objectives may necessarily involve trading off

    performance in relation to other stated objectives. Regulatory statutes, in

    addition, often give regulators scope for exercising judgement and devising

    solutions. (They do this because legislators generally have limited information

    and expertise in specialist areas and, though knowing that there is a problem,

    tend not to know how to solve it.) It is, in such cases, impossible to point to

    clear objectives. Legislators, furthermore, may deliberately avoid setting down

    precise objectives because they want regulators to have the freedom to cope

    with problems as they arise in the futureto meet the emergent challenges

    of new risks, innovative operations, novel technologies and so on. For all of

    these reasons, regulators are seldom, if ever, involved in the mechanical

    transmission of statutory objectives into results on the ground,12 and the

    mandate benchmark, though of relevance, will rarely provide an easy answer

    to questions of legitimation.

    ACCOUNTABILITY

    Regulators with imprecise mandates may, nevertheless, claim that they

    deserve the support of the public because they are properly accountable to,

    and controlled by, democratic institutions. Thus, a regulatory agency might

    claim that it is accountable for its interpretation of its mandate to a represen-

    tative body and that this oversight renders its exercise of powers acceptable.13

    A difculty with this criterion is that controversy will often attend the

    selection of the individuals and bodies that provide accountability. If Parlia-

    ment itself or another elected institution is not the body holding the regulator

    to account, then the arrangement may be criticized as unrepresentative.

    Where control is exercised by certain institutions (e.g. courts), the compe-