c.b. daly - new light on wittgenstein2

Upload: dapiperno

Post on 19-Feb-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/23/2019 C.B. Daly - New Light on Wittgenstein2

    1/35

    II

    New

    Li8ht

    o

    Witt8enstein

    P RT Two

    5. The Philosophical Investigations

    IN the first part

    of

    this

    article 221

    three sections have already been

    devoted to the Investigations: 1, Mr. Gellner: or the Wittgenstein

    that Never Was ; 2

    The

    Critique of the Tractatus ;

    3 The

    Disorders

    of

    Philosophy'.

    5 4 The Critique of Psychologism

    A favourite area for critical exploration by Wittgenstein was the

    area of our concepts about mental acts and states. He constantly

    criticised the idea that there are hidden and elusive, interior mental

    states, discernible only by the subject by dint of intensive intro

    spection. In this domain, his target was always G.

    E.

    Moore.

    Moore had written in

    1903

    (and the method remained a character

    istic

    with

    him):

    When we refer to introspection and try to discover what the sensation

    of blue is, it is very easy to suppose that we have before us only a

    single term. The term '

    blue

    is easy enough to distinguish, but the

    other element which I have called ' consciousness' is extremely

    difficult to

    fix. .

    Though philosophers have recognised that

    something distinct is meant by consciousness, they have never yet

    had a clear conception of what that something is. They have

    not

    been able to hold

    it

    and blue before their minds and to compare

    them in the same way in which they can compare

    blue

    and

    green .

    [Because] . . . the moment we try to fix

    our

    attention upon

    consciousness and to see what, distinctly it is, it seems to vanish

    [It

    is] as if it were diaphanous. Yet it can be distinguished if we

    look attentively enough. . . . My main object in this paragraph

    has been to try to make the reader see it; but I fear I shall have

    succeeded very ll

    222

    I t is to this that Wittgenstein is alluding when he writes:

    Here it

    is

    easy to get into that dead-end in philosophy, where one

    believes that the difficulty

    of

    the task consists in our having to

    describe phenomena that are hard to get hold of, the present

    experience that slips quickly by, or something of the kind. Where

    we find ordinary language too crude, and it looks as if we were

    having to do, not with the phenomena of everyday, but with ones that

    1

    See Philosophical Studies, X, 1960, pp. 5-49

    The Refutation of Idealism', in Philosophical Studies. Kegan Paul. London.

    1922, pp. 20, 25.

    28

  • 7/23/2019 C.B. Daly - New Light on Wittgenstein2

    2/35

    NEW LIGHT ON WITTGENSTEIN-II

    29

    easily elude us and, in their coming to

    be

    and passing away,

    produce those others as an average effect .

    223

    This idea

    of

    philosophy as mind-gazing is anathema to

    Wittgenstein. t is the pursuit

    of

    a mirage. Always, on the point

    of being got into focus, the mental state vanishes.

    I t is

    as if one

    had altered the adjustment

    of

    a microscope . Instead of

    the

    inner

    experience

    of

    intending, which one is trying to recall, something

    else comes into

    view

    224

    Always, we are finding

    ourselves

    as if

    we

    had to repair a torn spider s web with

    our

    fingers

    .225

    This

    type

    of

    philosophy illustrates perfectly for Wittgenstein the complex

    of errors which for him characterise classical philosophy.

    I t

    involves

    the mistake of supposing that there is one single valid analysis of a

    mental-process proposition, one single definition

    of

    each mental

    concept; and that, when the definition has been found,

    we

    shall

    have exact and final understanding

    of

    the

    hidden

    essence

    of

    thinking , knowing , willing

    and the rest.

    226

    t is

    not necessary to attempt to follow Wittgenstein s discussions

    in any detail here. A rapid survey will show how his own new

    way of philosophising emerges by reaction against the old. There

    is

    a long critique

    of

    the concept

    of

    a private language in which

    a person might be supposed to write down or give vocal expression

    to his inner experiences-his feelings, moods and the rest-for his

    private use .

    227 In

    the course

    of

    these investigations, Wittgenstein

    is able

    to

    kill several birds at once: the grammatical-logical

    223

    436 (the concluding quotation is from St. Augustine). Moore s two hands

    argument, and his assertion of the evident truth of the statement, The Earth has

    existed in the last five minutes (from A Defence

    of

    Common Sense .), are criticised

    in II, xi (p. 221); the former, on the ground that if I don t believe in my hands I

    needn t believe in my eyes either (which seems very common-sense ); the latter,

    on the ground

    that nobody

    in a common-sense mood would ever say such a thing.

    On

    the personal relations, and philosophical disagreement between Moore and.

    Wittgenstein, see Malcolm, Memoir, pp.

    33-4,66-7,73,79-80,87-92;

    and von Wright,

    ibid.,

    p. 15.

    224

    645.

    225 106.

    226 See 91-2: I t may come to look as if there were something like a final analysis

    of

    our forms

    of

    language, and so a single completely resolved

    form of

    every expression.

    That is, as if our usual forms

    of

    expression were essentially unanalysed; as if there

    were something hidden

    in

    them that had to be

    brought

    to light. When this is done,

    the expression

    is

    completely clarified and our problem solved. t can also be put

    like this:

    we

    eliminate misunderstandings by making our expressions more exact;

    but now it may look as if we were moving towards a particular state, a state

    of

    complete exactness; and as if this were the real goal of our investigation . . .

    This finds expression in questions as

    to

    the essence

    of

    language,

    of

    propositions,

    of

    thought. They see in the essence something that lies beneath the surface.

    Something

    that

    lies within, which we see when we look into the thing, and which an

    analysis digs out . . . . And the answer to these questions is to be given once for

    all; and independently

    of

    any future experience Cfr. II, xi (p. 225).

    I t

    will be

    noted

    that the Moorean concept

    of

    analysis, criticised here, has affinity with the

    Russell

    and Tractatus

    type of analysis which

    we

    have seen Wittgenstein also rejecting.

    G. A.

    Paul

    says: Wittgenstein criticises the notion

    of

    analysis in a way that has

    quite changed philosophy

    The Revolution

    n

    Philosophy,

    p. 88).

    22,

    243-323; also 380; 398 If

  • 7/23/2019 C.B. Daly - New Light on Wittgenstein2

    3/35

    30

    PHILOSOPHICAL

    STUDIES

    confusion whereby 'expressing a judgment' is assimilated to

    'expressing a thought' and this to 'expressing a pain 228 the

    Moorean idea

    of

    a secret inner thing in my mind which only I

    can see; the Russellian idea

    of

    the logically propel' name, or the

    private ostensive definition. Against Moore's notion, he argues

    that a thing in a sealed mind-box, which nobody could ever

    see

    or know except he who has the box, could not even be seen or

    known by the latter; because to recognise and identify it, he needs

    words, and words are public:

    '

    sensation is a

    wOld

    of our

    common language, not

    of

    one intelligible to

    me

    alone'.

    229

    Against

    both Moore and Russell (and incidentally against any implicit

    solipsism) he makes the important point that mental-process words,

    being part of language, which is necessarily public, are situated

    from the beginning in an inter-personal and public world.

    230

    All

    this section

    is

    an excellent example of Wittgenstein's technique of

    appealing to common-sense against 'philosophy'.

    A related and continuously reiterated theme is that knowing,

    sensing, speaking, intending, etc., are not

    tw

    distinguishable things

    (as Moore's introspectionist technique suggested), namely a public

    and a private thing, a

    coarse

    physical and a hidden mental

    thing.

    23oa

    Since

    we

    can know only what

    we

    can identify by criteria,

    describe and name, and since criteria, descriptions and names are

    public, then, so far from its being true that ' private' mental states

    alone are infallibly known, the truth

    is

    that ' private' mental states,

    in the sense intended, are unknowable. To determine what knowing

    is we must therefore look at the multitude

    of

    accomplishments

    which we call knowing, the manifold circumstances in which we

    say , I know', Now I know how to

    go on

    etc.

    231

    The same

    is

    true

    of

    thinking:

    it

    is ' not an incorporeal process which lends life

    and sense to speaking and which

    it

    would be possible to detach

    from speaking, rather as the Devil took the shadow of Schlemiehl

    from the ground'.

    232

    'Understanding' too is quite distorted

    if

    we make

    it

    an esoteric, private, unsayable mystery. Understanding

    means being able to say something, to do something, being able

    , to

    go

    on

    ;

    and we cannot get a right view

    of

    it until we survey

    the situations in which

    we

    use this sort

    of

    language.

    233

    Reading

    is not an overt performance shadowed by some interior monitoring

    228

    304-5, 308, 317, 501.

    2 293;

    261; cfr. 258.

    230 258 insists that I cannot identify my own sensation without criteria, communi

    cable to and accessible to others. Compare 343, 246, 260-3, 286, 290-1, 322. On

    the impossibility of a private ostensive definition see 380, 398.

    230

    a

    In the Brown Book, he

    had

    spoken of the curious superstition', the kind

    of general disease

    of

    thinking which always looks for (and finds) what would

    be

    called a mental state from which

    all our

    acts spring as from a reservoir . See p. 143.

    231

    152-4, 179-182, 527-9. Compare Malcolm,

    Memoir

    pp. 87 tr.

    232

    339; cfr. 327-341. Compare the

    Blue Book

    pp. 37-65.

    233

    152_5

    514, 520, 527-533; 536-9; cfr. the Brown Book po. 113-4.

    A

  • 7/23/2019 C.B. Daly - New Light on Wittgenstein2

    4/35

    NEW LIGHT ON WITTGENSTEIN-II

    31

    activity.234

    Negation

    is

    not a ' mental activity' and is not always

    the same activity.235 There is no single occult essence of 'meaning';

    we mean many things by meaning and they are all embodied things.

    Occult processes, supposed to be known only to

    me,

    cannot be

    known even to me and cannot have meaning even for me. Nothing

    has meaning except what I can say, and words are not intimate

    but inter-personal. Wittgenstein concludes Part I by the sharp

    saying: N o ~ h i n g is more wrong-headed than calling meaning a

    mental activity. Unless, that is, one is setting out to produce

    confusion

    .236

    The same applies to the language of willing. Willing is not an

    inner experience separable from its

    object

    '. Willing is doing

    something (even if it

    is

    only

    trying ')

    willingly.237

    To put 'willing'

    in the mind and 'doing' in the world

    is

    to make willing inefficacious,

    the will irresponsible and the world 'independent of my will'.

    Wittgenstein had reason to know: he had done chis himself in the

    Tractatus

    and thus excluded the possibility

    of

    ethical propositions.

    38

    We must not sublime' willing or ethics, any more than logic;

    that

    is

    to say, we must not separate them from experience.

    The same is true of ' believing',

    hoping ,

    'expecting', 'wishing',

    intending .239 t is true

    of

    every piece

    of

    mental language

    where

    we

    are tempted to postulate an inward process

    or

    picture

    or a ' mental image shadowing the act referred to. Such inward

    pictures' cannot be described (for

    if

    they can, they are not

    inward

    in the sense intended); therefore they cannot be meaningful or

    relevant or real. Furthermore, in a wider sense of ' mental image ,

    where it means imagery accompanying meaning or language, this

    varies from person to person, and in the same person, has no

    permanent or intrinsic connection with the same word; therefore

    it cannot be what we mean.240

    Part

    II

    is mainly taken up with investigations of this sort.

    Recourse to inner processes' or inner feelings' to explain

    cognitive processes is repeatedly pronounced irrelevant and mistaken.

    Doubt, supposition, are not feelings ( if-feelings Of other). I

    can doubt or suppose without having these feelings. I can have

    the feelings without doubting

    or

    supposing. Even if someone had

    234

    156-165, 167-8; efr. the Brown Book pp. 120-1.

    235

    547-557.

    236

    693; efr. 322, 358, 543-4, 558-561, 666

    if.

    Compare the

    Brown Book pp.

    78-9, 172-3; and Malcolm, Memoir pp. 87-8.

    237

    611-630.

    Compare the Brown Book

    pp. 100-4, 110-116, 150-2.

    238

    6.373, 6.42. Wittgenstein is formally rejecting this view in 620. Compare 337.

    239

    437_441, 574-592.

    240

    449 if. 518-520, 598; err. 213, 305-8, 314-6.

    Compare the Blue Book

    pp.

    48 if. 78-9; the Brown Book pp. 167 fT In part, at least, of his critique of

    psychologism, Wittgenstein had as precursor Bradley. See R. A. Wollheim's, F.

    H. Bradley , in The Revolution in Philosophy pp. 12-25; and the same author s

    F H. Bradley Penguin Books, 1959, pp. 17-43.

    B

  • 7/23/2019 C.B. Daly - New Light on Wittgenstein2

    5/35

    32

    PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES

    a particular capacity only when, and only

    as

    long

    as

    he had a

    particular feeling, the feeling would

    not

    be the capacity

    .241

    Similarly mental images that accompany meaning are not meaning.

    4

    , Being certain

    is

    not a certain feeling .

    43

    A hesitant assertion

    is not an assertion of my state

    of

    hesitancy.244

    There

    is

    an important section devoted to Moore s paradox

    about I believe

    that

    x is y . This proposition was a fatal

    stumbling-block

    to

    Russell s truth-functional theory of propositions;

    because the truth of x is y , is irrelevant to the truth of I believe

    that x is y

    :

    it can be true that I believe, but what I believe may

    be false. Russell had two ways of escape; either to make

    , believing , as a mental fact, a peculiar and subsistent logical

    species (and thus Platonic gbosts return);

    or

    to explain believing

    behaviouristically.245 The latter is, in effect, what Ryle does with

    belief. Wittgenstein rejects both expedients (and by anticipation

    rejects Ryle s dispositional behaviourism). He does not solve

    the ploblem; but he makes it impossible to maintain either that

    I

    believe that

    . .

    . is a statement about me; or that when I say

    , I believe that

    . .

    . , I am declaring my disposition to behave in

    certain ways246; or making sets of testable hypothetical and semi

    hypothetical propositions

    .247

    The section

    is

    a good example

    of

    Wittgenstein s dictum:

    Say what you choose, so long as it does

    not

    prevent you from

    seeing the facts. (And when you see them, there is a good deal

    that you will

    not say.)248

    Soi-disant Wittgensteinians had some pretext from the language

    of Wittgenstein when they poured scorn on ghostly mind-stories,

    inner-world myths , mystery-mongering , etc., and opted for a

    tough, one-world-and-no-nonsense behaviourism or quasi

    behaviourism.

    49

    There are many passages in which Wittgenstein

    seems to pour equal scorn on all spirit- or soul-

    or

    mind-language.

    He speaks derisively

    of the

    conception

    of

    thought as a gaseous

    medium .250 He speaks scornfully of a hocus-pocus which can

    be performed only by the soul .251 He seems to suggest that all

    talk about spirit is due to failure to find the right

    bodily

    language,

    2

  • 7/23/2019 C.B. Daly - New Light on Wittgenstein2

    6/35

    NEW LIGHT ON WITTGENSTEIN-II

    33

    or

    failure to understand the bodily language we do use.

    252

    Talk

    about' mind' or spirit' seems for him to be typical philosophical

    illusion, such as arises when language goes on holiday . This

    is

    what happens when the philosopher tries to practice psychologist s

    introspection and when, in order to discover what

    'self '

    means

    'he

    says the word

    self

    to himself and tries to analyse its

    meaning

    .253

    t is in a similar' free-floating state, when I try to be conscious

    of consciousness without being conscious of anything else, that I

    get the ' feeling of an unbridgeable gulf between consciousness and

    brain process , a feeling of a difference in kind accompanied

    by a slight giddiness .

    254

    t is then that I get the sense

    of

    the

    queerness

    of

    thought.

    255

    t

    is then that I have the emotion

    of

    awe

    and mystery-at something

    deep, hidden,

    a sense lying far in the

    background .256 But, Wittgenstein proclaims, this

    is

    illusion. Let

    us put our words back into gear, back into use; let us, we may

    say,

    put our

    minds back to their work of being conscious

    of things,

    and then the illusion and the giddiness vanish. There is nothing

    'queet '

    or

    'deep' or

    'hidden

    .257

    Everything lies open to

    view .258

    If

    we try to lay bare the essence

    of

    thought by stripping

    off the

    'coverings' of actual thinking, then we simply find that

    thought itself has disappeared.

    ' In

    order to find the real artichoke,

    we divested it

    of

    its leaves .258

    a

    We should be

    talking'

    about the

    spatial and temporal phenomena of language, not about some non

    spatial, non-temporal phantasm ' .259 Our proper concern is not

    with curiosities, but with the' natural history

    of

    human beings' ;26

    for mental-words' are as much part of our natural history as

    252 36: 'Because we

    cannot

    specify nyone bodily action . . . we say that a

    spiritual

    [mental, intellectual] activity corresponds

    to

    these words. Where our

    language suggests a body and there is none: there, we should like to say is a spirit.

    Compare

    196, 363; the

    Blue Book,

    p. 47:

    'When

    we perceive that a substantive

    is not used as what we should call the name of an object we can't help saying

    to

    ourselves that it is the name

    of an

    aethereal object. A clearing-up

    of

    the grammar

    will dissolve the problem, in the language of the Blue Book (which does not recur

    in this form in the Investigations):

    'This

    is a hint as to how the problem

    of

    the

    two materials,

    mind and matter,

    is going to dissolve.

    2.3413 (referring to William James). Wittgenstein read James a good deal and

    seems to take him as typical

    of

    psychology. See 342, 610, xi. These references

    are

    usually critical;

    but

    he admired James as a philosopher; see J.

    A.

    Passmore,

    A Hundred Years of Philosophy,

    428; Dr. Drury in

    The Listener,

    28th January,

    1960. See also 404-412.

    25