the psychology of insanity

140

Upload: bernard-hart

Post on 27-Dec-2016

215 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Psychology of Insanity
Page 2: The Psychology of Insanity

THE PSYCHOLOGY OFINSANITY

Page 3: The Psychology of Insanity

BY BERNARD HART

PSYCHOPATHOLOGYIts Development and its Place inMedicine

Page 4: The Psychology of Insanity

THE PSYCHOLOGY OFINSANITY

BY

BERNARD HARTC.B.E., M.D. (LOND.), F.R.G.P. (LOND.)

Fellow of University College, London

Consulting Physician in Psychological Medicine

University College Hospital and

National Hospital, Queen Square, London

FIFTH EDITION

CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS

Page 5: The Psychology of Insanity

CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESSCambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore,

Sao Paulo, Delhi

Cambridge University PressThe Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK

Published in the United States of America byCambridge University Press, New York

www.cambridge.orgInformation on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521114691

© Cambridge University Press 1912, 1957

This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exceptionand to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,no reproduction of any part may take place without the written

permission of Cambridge University Press.

First published 1912Second edition 1914Third edition 1916

Reprinted 1918, 1919 (twice), 1920, 1921, 1922, 1923, 1925,1928, 1929

Fourth edition 1930Reprinted 1936, 1941, 1943, 1946, 1949, 1952

Fifth edition 1957Reprinted 1958, 1974

This digitally printed version 2009

A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library

ISBN 978-0-521-05219-1 hardbackISBN 978-0-521-11469-1 paperback

Page 6: The Psychology of Insanity

PREFACE TO FIRST EDITION

T H I S book lays no claim to be a comprehensive treatise uponthe psychology of insanity. The number of independent schoolsof thought existing at the present day, and the fundamentaldivergence in their methods of investigation, make it obviouslyimpossible to compress such a treatise into the limits of a smallvolume. All that has been attempted here is the presentationof certain recent developments in abnormal psychology whichhave already yielded results of fundamental importance, andwhich seem to offer an exceptionally promising field forfurther investigation.

An endeavour has been made to develop the subject-matterof the book in a systematic manner, so that the general prin-ciples which it is sought to establish may appear in as clear alight as possible. The adoption of the systematic method in awork of this size, however, renders a somewhat dogmatic modeof presentation inevitable. It is necessary, therefore, to warnthe reader that many of the theories to which he will be intro-duced have not as yet been firmly established, and that theyare to be regarded rather as suggestive hypotheses which willultimately require considerable alteration and improvement.

It must be clearly understood, moreover, that no attempthas been made to cover the whole field of insanity. On thecontrary, certain sections of that field have been more or lessarbitrarily selected, mainly on the ground that they yieldfruitful results to psychological methods of investigation. Iconfidently anticipate that in the future these methods willhave a far wider application, but in the present state of ourknowledge it must be frankly admitted that there are wholetracts of insanity in which they have only a very limited utility.This confession is all the more necessary on account of thetendency to unduly extensive generalisation evident in thework of many recent investigators. In view of the enormouscomplexity of mental processes, and the youthfulness of

Page 7: The Psychology of Insanity

psychology, it is best to realise that progress must inevitablybe slow, and that we must be content to feel our way to thescientific laws of the future.

A very large number of the general principles enunciatedin this book are due to the genius of Prof. Freud of Vienna,probably the most original and fertile thinker who has yetentered the field of abnormal psychology. Although, however,I cannot easily express the extent to which I am indebted tohim, I am by no means prepared to embrace the whole of thevast body of doctrines which Freud and his followers havenow laid down. Much of this is in my opinion unproven, anderected upon an unsubstantial foundation. On the other hand,many of Freud's fundamental principles are becoming moreand more widely accepted, and the evidence in their favour israpidly increasing. In the present volume I have endeavouredto introduce only those principles which have already acquireda satisfactory claim to recognition.

Among many other authorities to whose writings I havehad recourse, Dr Jung of Zurich, Prof. Janet of Paris, Prof.Karl Pearson, and the late Prof. Krafft-Ebing must be spe-cially mentioned. Lastly, I am very greatly indebted to Mr W.Trotter's two papers on 'Herd Instinct', published in theSociological Review for 1908 and 1909.

I have to thank Dr Edward Mapother for much valuableassistance in the preparation of the manuscript and the revisingof the proofs.

BERNARD H A R TSeptember 1912

VI

Page 8: The Psychology of Insanity

PREFACE TO FIFTH EDITION

THIS book was first published in 1912 and, although it hassince been many times reprinted, no material alteration hasbeen made in the original text. Nor, in the present edition,will any such material alteration be found. Some minormodifications have been incorporated, but these are in themain purely verbal in character. The book therefore remains,and must be judged as, a product of 1912.

In these days of rapid advance in every field of scientificendeavour such a policy requires some justification, and thisis no less necessary in the field of psychology, where the growthof the present century has been almost revolutionary in itscharacter and extent. The decision to leave the book in its ori-ginal form has been based on three grounds. In the first placeit is concerned with elementary and general principles whichhave been relatively unaffected by the advances of subsequentyears, because those advances have involved the addition offurther stories to the building rather than a remaking of thefoundations. In the second place, the development of the sub-ject has been so luxuriant, and the divergencies of thoughtcharacterising the different schools have become so markedand so complex, that an attempt to bring the text satisfactorilyup-to-date after the lapse of more than forty years would be aformidable task, and one which would practically involve,not a new edition, but a new book. Moreover, such an attemptwould completely traverse the very modest aim which it wasoriginally sought to achieve. In the third place, perhaps themost cogent justification for the decision to leave the originaltext essentially unaltered, is that the constant reprintings, bothin this country and America, show that the book has preservedan appeal throughout all these years, in spite of the date whichit bears.

It is advisable, however, to amplify the grounds which havebeen stated. The essential aim of the book when it appeared

vii

Page 9: The Psychology of Insanity

in 1912 was to illustrate how the 'psychological conception'which had gradually developed round about the turn of thecentury through the work of Janet to the principles of Freudand Jung, served to illuminate the phenomena both of thenormal mind and of mental disorder. That illumination, veryapparent and striking to the student who had hitherto beennourished on the somewhat arid psychology of former days,was based on concepts which were fairly simple in theirstructure, and which have now indeed become largelycommonplaces. Moreover, the dynamic principles, which weowe to the genius of Freud, were at that time fairly uniformlyheld by the analytical school of thought. In that very year of1912, however, serious rifts developed in that school. Jungand Adler, hitherto enthusiastic exponents of Freud's views,diverged radically both from those views and from each other,and ultimately founded quite independent schools of thought.Nevertheless these divergencies were essentially dependentupon the seeking of deeper concepts than those relativelysimple and superficial ones to which this book is mainlyconfined, and the latter therefore have not been very materiallyaffected.

Although no fundamental change has been made in theoriginal text, there have been some purely verbal alterationsin subsequent editions. These are mainly the substitution of'mental hospital' for 'asylum', of'insane patient' for 'luna-tic', and in many places of 'mental disorder' for 'insanity'.These call for some explanation. In the first place, what Ihave termed rather unhappily in chapter 1 the 'politicalconception', and which would perhaps be better termed the'sociological conception', already far advanced in 1912, hassince advanced considerably further. It is now universallyaccepted that the insane are patients suffering from diseasejust as much as other patients, and that the prejudices formerlydirected against them have no shred of justification. Toemphasise this change in attitude the old word 'asylum',whose original meaning was entirely innocent and benevolentbut which had acquired sinister associations in the eighteenth

viii

Page 10: The Psychology of Insanity

and nineteenth centuries, was abandoned in the developmentsof the present century and replaced by the term 'mentalhospital' in which the new attitude to insanity was madeclear. The change is further manifested by the fact that in themental hospital of today a very large number of patients,sometimes the majority, enter the hospital voluntarily andwithout any legal duress.

Next, one of the aims of the book was to develop the thesisthat the insane patient was a fellow-man, that his mentalprocesses were not completely chaotic and inexplicable butonly variations or exaggerations of processes to be found inthe normal mind. In pursuance of this aim the word * lunatic',originally the offspring of an absurd superstition and alreadylargely obsolescent in 1912, was deliberately employed in theedition of 1912 to underline the old attitude to insanity whichthe book sought to pillory. Nowadays, however, there is noneed to attack what has become an open door; tjie term* lunatic' would be completely out of place, and has thereforebeen discontinued.

Finally, the substitution in many places of the term ' mentaldisorder' for 'insanity* has arisen in this way. As has just beenexplained, an original aim of this book was to show that themental processes of the insane could be paralleled by examplesdrawn from the normal mind and from minor mental disordersor, as it may be put, to demonstrate the 'sanity of insanity'.Hence, although it was implied that the processes involvedranged in a continuous series from those occurring in thenormal mind through the minor mental disorders to pro-nounced insanity, the latter term tended unduly to dominatethe picture. In later editions, and in response to criticismsthat the concepts of the book were as interesting when appliedto the normal mind or to the minor disorders, the term'insanity' was in many places replaced by the general term* mental disorder' in order to make clear that no sharp linescould be placed between the normal and the minor mentaldisorders on the one hand, nor on the other hand betweenthe latter and definite insanity, but that we were dealing

ix

Page 11: The Psychology of Insanity

with a continuous series, with the normal at one end and thosegross derangements coming under the head of insanity atthe other. This procedure has been adhered to in the presentedition.

In the fourth edition an Introduction was incorporatedwhich aimed at describing the historical development ofpsychopathology from its beginnings to the stage it had reachedat the time the book was originally published in 1912, inorder that the reader might appreciate the foundations uponwhich the book was built. The greater part of this Introductionhas been included in the present edition, with some modifica-tions and the addition of a few remarks upon the develop-ment which has occurred in the subject since the first editionappeared.

BERNARD HARTJune 1956

Page 12: The Psychology of Insanity

CONTENTS

Prefaces . . . . . . . page v

Introduction to Fifth Edition . . . . . i

Chapter i T H E H I S T O R Y O F M E N T A L D I S O R D E R . , 1 5

n T H E P S Y C H O L O G I C A L C O N C E P T I O N OF M E N T A L

D I S O R D E R . . . . . . 2 1

m T H E P H E N O M E N A OF M E N T A L D I S O R D E R . 2 8

I V DISSOCIATION . . , . . 3 9

V C O M P L E X E S . . . . . . 5 2

V I C O N F L I C T . . . . . . 6 5

VII R E P R E S S I O N . . . . . . 7 2

VIII MANIFESTATIONS OF R E P R E S S E D C O M P L E X E S . 7 8

I X P R O J E C T I O N . . . . . . 9 O

X T H E I R R A T I O N A L I T Y OF T H E I N S A N E . . 9 6

X I P H A N T A S Y . . . . . I O 6

XII T H E SIGNIFICANCE OF C O N F L I C T . . I I 9

Index . . . . . . . , . 1 2 5

XI

Page 13: The Psychology of Insanity
Page 14: The Psychology of Insanity

INTRODUCTION TO FIFTH EDITION

T H I S introduction seeks to put before the reader a generalsketch of the history of psychopathology from its beginnings tothe position which it held in 1912, in order that he may beable to appreciate the place in the subject of the principlesdescribed in this book. It therefore attempts to cover a widerfield than is proper to an introduction, and for this reasonthe uninstructed layman will probably find it more intelligibleand useful if it is read after rather than before the book.

DEVELOPMENT OF PSYGHOPATHOLOGY PRIOR TO JANET

Psychopathology, the science which attempts to explain theproblems of mental disorder by psychological principles andlaws, is of comparatively recent growth, and can hardly besaid to have existed before the last quarter of the nineteenthcentury. The remarkable phenomena produced by Mesmerand the other ' magnetisers' had aroused a widespread interesta hundred years earlier, and later investigators had demon-strated that these phenomena were due, not to the magnets,but to the suggestions communicated by the operator. These'suggestions' were clearly causes of a psychological order,and it was therefore known that psychological causes werecapable of bringing about definite changes in mind and body.Until the time of Gharcot (1825-93), however, this conceptionhad not been applied to the problem of disease, and we owe tothat investigator the first formulation of the view that certaindisorders were due simply to the action of'ideas'. This state-ment may be said to have been the foundation stone of modernpsychopathology, and it led to a series of investigations whichrapidly extended our knowledge and understanding of theso-called 'functional nervous disorders', including hysteria,neurasthenia, and other allied conditions. It was soon appre-ciated that in this group psychological factors of various kinds

Page 15: The Psychology of Insanity

played a dominant part in the causation, and an attemptbegan to be made to formulate that part in exact terms.Amongst the psychological factors concerned an importantplace had clearly to be assigned to 'suggestion5, that is to say,the implantation in the patient's mind of certain ideas andbeliefs, and their resultant effect in the production of varioussymptoms and disturbances. Suggestion, however, was aprocess so vague and general that it could not furnish a reallysatisfactory explanation of complex disorders, and investigatorssought to discover further psychological laws which wouldrender the incidence and nature of these disorders moreintelligible, and which would moreover also explain howsuggestion produced its results.

WORK OF JANET

The first noteworthy advance in this direction was made byJanet with his conception of 'dissociation'. This conception,which is described in chapter iv of the book, was "developedat the end of last century as the result of a brilliant series ofresearches, and it forms a milestone of fundamental importancein the progress of psychopathology. Janet showed that con-sciousness does not necessarily consist in a single and homo-geneous stream, but that it is sometimes split into a number ofmore or less independent currents, and that the dissociationthereby produced explains a large number of phenomena,not only in hysteria and other disorders, but in the processesof our everyday mental life. This conception has proved tobe extraordinarily fertile as a weapon of understanding, but itis only capable of taking us a certain distance along the road.The further question naturally arises as to why dissociationstake place, and the conception of dissociation in itself furnishesno answer to this question. Such an answer will only be forth-coming if we can obtain a knowledge of the dynamics of themind, that is to say, a knowledge of the forces which producethe various phenomena of mental process and the laws of theiraction.

Page 16: The Psychology of Insanity

THE PLAGE OF FREUD

The first consistent attempt to advance to a dynamic point ofview was made by Freud, who is unquestionably the domi-nating figure in modern psychopathology, though the precisevalue and reliability of the vast structure which he has nowerected is still a matter of doubt and dispute. The principlesdescribed in the later chapters of this book are in the maindirectly due to him, and for the rest have been developedfrom the new points of view which his genius originated.Nevertheless the angle of approach to the subject and themethod of treatment in the book diverged even at the time ofits publication in many important respects from the pathfollowed by Freud. Freud's later work has tended to accentuatethese divergences, while it has added much new knowledgeand even more new theory to the original structure. His doc-trines now occupy so prominent a place in modern psychology,moreover, that they demand consideration, not merely as acontribution to the building of our subject, but as a more orless complete system of thought, laying down its own postulatesand laws, and relatively independent of other modes ofapproach. For these reasons, therefore, it is necessary that thereader of this book should appreciate the mode and extent inwhich its viewpoint differed from Freud's position as it stoodin 1912, and the development which his work has undergonein the years which have since elapsed. An attempt to achievethis purpose will be made by giving here a brief summary ofFreud's views in their historical perspective; but such a sketchmust necessarily be very inadequate, and it is hoped that it willbe amplified by reference to the special literature of the subject.

THE DEVELOPMENT OF FREUD 5 CONCEPTIONS

In 1880 Josef Breuer of Vienna investigated a case of hysteriain which he found that the symptoms were due to certainmemories of which the patient was herself unconscious, andthat a cure was effected when these memories were brought

3

Page 17: The Psychology of Insanity

once more into consciousness. Freud collaborated with Breuerin further work along the lines which this discovery suggested,and from that moment he developed gradually but contin-uously the great structure of theory and practice which is nowassociated with his name.

It will be noted that almost from the beginning certainfundamental principles were already apparent. These prin-ciples were, firstly, that the mind contained more than con-sciousness, and that memories could exist and continuallyproduce effects, although those memories were divorced fromand inaccessible to consciousness. The mind therefore consistednot only of conscious but also of unconscious processes.Secondly, the memories shut out from consciousness must besubjected to some force which actively prevented their appear-ance in consciousness, for they were not capable of beingrecalled by any ordinary means. This active force was termed'resistance', and it was a plausible inference that the forcewhich did not permit of the excluded memories enteringconsciousness had originally been responsible for that veryexclusion.

The next step was the determination of the way in whichthis exclusion, or *repression* as it was technically termed,arose and why it was being maintained. Investigation ledFreud to conclude that repression occurred because of thesimultaneous existence in the mind of two incompatiblestrivings and the attempt of the mind to get rid of this intoler-able strain by excluding one of the opponents from conscious-ness. This opponent then passed into the unconscious regions ofthe mind, where it was still capable of activity but could notdirectly appear upon the conscious stage. The situation couldtherefore now be depicted in this way. The hysterical symp-toms, for example paralyses or anaesthesias, were producedby mental factors which were unconscious but active; theywere unconscious because they had been incompatible withother forces in the mind and had been repressed from con-sciousness as a method of avoiding the conflict which wasotherwise inevitable. The symptoms thus served to express,

Page 18: The Psychology of Insanity

albeit in an indirect and distorted manner, a striving whichalthough existing in the mind was not allowed to appear inconsciousness. The distortion was due to the repressing forces,and the symptoms could therefore be said to constitute the end-product produced by the interaction of the repressed andrepressing forces.

The various ways in which this interaction occurred wereworked out in detail, and a number of 'mechanisms' wereformulated which described the mode in which the forcesconcerned caused the appearance of a 'symptom5. Several ofthese mechanisms are dealt with in the pages of this book(chapters vm and ix).

It was found, moreover, not only that the processes whichwere being discovered were to be discerned in hysteria, but alsothat they were responsible for the symptoms observed in othertypes of nervous and mental disorder, and were capable ofexplaining many of the psychological phenomena of everydaylife. The investigation of dreams proved to be particularlyfruitful in this respect, and led to the discovery that theirstructure and mode of development were essentially analogousto those observed in the production of neurotic symptoms.This discovery was of great practical importance, because itwas found that a study of the dreams of a patient enabled theinvestigator to elucidate the nature of the forces acting in themind, and hence could be used as a method of ascertaining thefacts necessary for the patient's treatment.

It has been mentioned that Freud's theories involved theassumption that the mind did not only consist of consciousness,but that it also comprised processes of which the individualhimself was completely unaware, although they were capableof activities otherwise comparable with those observed inconsciousness. This assumption of the existence of an uncon-scious mind was elaborated by Freud into a new conceptionof mental topography. He held that three regions existed in themind—the conscious, the foreconscious, and the unconscious.In the conscious region were contained those processes whichcomprise consciousness in the ordinary sense of the term. In

Page 19: The Psychology of Insanity

the foreconscious were processes which, though not consciousat the moment, might immediately become so by a simple actof recall. In the unconscious were processes which not onlywere not conscious at the moment, but could not become so byany ordinary means. Between the unconscious and the otherregions was a barrier which allowed no direct passage, butthrough which the unconscious processes could obtain egressprovided that they underwent modification and distortion.It will be seen that the passage from the other regions to theunconscious constituted 'repression', and that the barrier justdescribed constituted the resistance and distorting mediumwhich we have already observed in the mechanism ofsymptoms.

In working out the various ways in which the forces inter-acting in the mind produced the phenomena of dreams and thesymptoms of nervous disorder Freud naturally investigatedthe nature and origin of the forces concerned. He found thatforces derived from the sex instincts invariably played a parttherein, and in order to explain these facts he graduallydeveloped the elaborate sexual theory which has become thekernel of his doctrines.

Freud held that sex as we know it in the adult was the finalstage of a long process of evolution, which commenced inearliest infancy. During this evolution it underwent consider-able changes, so that the aduljt manifestations were radicallydifferent from the infantile, although the driving force or'libido' remained essentially the same throughout. In theinitial stages the libido was directed on to the individual him-self; later it became capable of being directed on to externalobjects. The first of these external objects was generally oneor other parent, predominantly the parent of the oppositesex. Later still the object of the libido was constituted by anindividual of the same sex, and only at the final stage did itattain the normal adult character, and become directed on toindividuals of the opposite sex. The libido was thus conceivedto pass through a succession of phases, autoerotic, parental,homosexual, and heterosexual. This development in the object

6

Page 20: The Psychology of Insanity

relationship of the libido was paralleled by an alteration in theparts of the body with which it was particularly associated.

Freud believed that this lengthy development of the libidocould miscarry in various ways, and that if such miscarriageoccurred perversions or disorders were produced. If thedevelopment failed to proceed beyond the homosexual stageone form of sexual perversion was manifested. If the changefrom one stage to the next was not properly completed, sothat the libido remained partially attached or * fixated5 to anearlier object relationship, while partially moving forwardsto the normal adult goal, then a state of conflict was produced,with the repression into the unconscious of these partiallydeveloped elements of the libido, and the resultant appearanceof neurotic disorder.

It has been said that Freud found that forces derived fromthe sex instincts invariably played a part in the conflicts andinteractions responsible for the phenomena of dreams andneurotic disorder or, as we may now express it, that anactivity of the libido was necessarily involved. Freud observed,however, that forces of an apparently quite different kindwere also concerned. These latter forces belonged to thepersonality or governing body of the organism, and collectivelyformed the * ego'; the ego would not permit the libido to pursuean untrammelled course, because control and inhibition werenecessary in the interests of that adaptation to the demandsof reality and environment which constituted the ego's chieffunction. Investigation showed, indeed, that the conflictsunderlying the symptoms of nervous disorder were essentiallydue to the struggle between the libido and the ego or, asFreud himself later expressed it, a nervous disorder develops'when the Ego loses its capacity to deal in some way or otherwith the Libido'. If this situation should occur, then conflictwould necessarily arise, and the attempt of the organism tosolve this conflict would lead to repressions, and the appearanceof'symptoms' in the way which has already been described.

Something must now be said of the method of investigationwhich Freud employed in building up his theories. This was

Page 21: The Psychology of Insanity

the method of' psychoanalysis', and it of course constitutes thekeystone of the whole structure. The method was developedas a means of obtaining access to the unconscious mentalprocesses which Freud believed to be responsible for the symp-toms observed in his patients. Clearly, as these processes wereby hypothesis unconscious, they could not be elicited by simpleinquiry or observation, and some special procedure had to bedevised. In his earliest researches Freud had used hypnotismfor this purpose, as it had long been known that by this meansaccess could be obtained to mental elements of which theindividual was completely unaware. Later, however, it wasfound that the unconscious processes could be elicited by amethod more widely applicable than hypnotism, and morefertile in its results. Freud noted that if the patient were askedto talk freely without making any attempt to control or directthe course of his thoughts, then these thoughts were deter-mined in part by unconscious factors, and the skilled investi-gator could conclude from the character of the thoughts thenature of the causal unconscious processes. Freud termed thismethod 'psychoanalysis', and gradually developed it into anelaborate weapon for the investigation and treatment of men-tal disorder. The whole of his work, including all the theoriesdeveloped in later years, is based upon its employment, andthe facts which have been elicited by its means.

Freud's earlier researches were mainly concerned withnervous disorders, but he had noted that processes closelycomparable to those found in these disorders were also to bediscerned in certain forms of insanity. This path was furtherexplored by Jung, at that time a follower of Freud, although hehas since developed an altogether independent school ofthought. Jung's investigation of dementia praecox, one of themost common forms of mental disorder, produced results ofthe first importance, and demonstrated that the psychologicallaws which Freud had discovered in his study of hysteriaplayed a prominent part in dementia praecox, although ofcourse fundamental differences existed between the twodisorders.

8

Page 22: The Psychology of Insanity

FREUD AND THE STANDPOINT ADOPTEDIN THIS BOOK

The point which we have now reached corresponds roughly tothe stage in Freud's development which had been achieved atthe time of the publication of this book. It has, of course, onlybeen possible to attempt a brief and inadequate sketch of theessential structure of Freud's theories, which had even at thattime already attained a great complexity, but it is hoped thata sufficiently clear picture will have been given to indicatebroadly the road along which he had travelled in his investi-gations. If this aim has been successfully achieved the readerwill have no difficulty in understanding the points in which thetreatment of the subject in this book differs from that followedby Freud.

In the first place, there is a notable difference in the angleof approach. Freud slowly and tentatively built up his theo-retical conceptions in accordance with the facts which werecontinuously elicited by his investigation of patients, and hemade no attempt to produce a systematic exposition of thesubject as a whole. In other words, he did not produce text-books, but a series of monographs. In this book, on the otherhand, a systematic exposition has been attempted, and theprinciples described have therefore been set out, not in theirhistorical perspective, but in accordance with the place whichbelongs to them in that exposition. Moreover, the subject hasbeen treated in a way which seeks constantly to demonstratethat the conceptions of psychopathology are constructedaccording to the rules which govern all progress in science, or,in other words, that they conform to the canons of scientificmethod. For this reason many of Freud's conceptions havebeen dealt with from a philosophical standpoint which doesnot correspond to the angle from which he himself had reachedthem, and which is in some respects not entirely compatiblewith that angle.

In the second place, the book does not profess to be a de-scription of Freud's theories. It covers only a small part of thefield which Freud has tilled, and many of the most important

Page 23: The Psychology of Insanity

sections of his work are not even mentioned. Moreover, itincludes such conceptions as dissociation, which either lieoutside his line of development or have only played a smalland relatively unimportant part therein.

As a result of these two main lines of divergence certainof Freud's conceptions are treated in this" book in a waywhich does not correspond to the place and importance theypossess in the building up of his system. For example, Freud'stopographical differentiation of the mind into conscious,preconscious, and unconscious regions has not been adopted.The existence of unconscious processes has been assumed asa conception necessary for the adequate explanation of thephenomena of consciousness, but these processes are regardedfrom a functional rather than a topographical standpoint, andthey have not the precise and peculiar character which Freudascribes to his 'Unconscious'.

Another example is furnished by the omission from the bookof any detailed consideration of the sex instincts. Freud's viewthat the sex instincts play a fundamental part in the conflictsresponsible for various disorders is indeed mentioned, but it ismerely put forward as a possible hypothesis concerning thenature of the ultimate factors involved. In Freud's own work,on the other hand, this hypothesis has been present almostfrom the beginning, and the development and activity of thelibido has formed the central structure round which all histheories have been built.

It must be understood, therefore, that this book does notreally occupy any definite place in the direct line of Freudianhistory, but is at once narrower and wider in its aim; narrowerin that it only deals with certain selected aspects of Freud'steaching, and wider in that it attempts to bring those aspectsinto relation with the lines of advance followed by otherinvestigators.

D E V E L O P M E N T O F P S Y G H O P A T H O L O G Y S I N G E I O , I 2

It has been explained in the Preface that any attempt to bringthe book up-to-date by amending the text, or by describing,

10

Page 24: The Psychology of Insanity

however briefly, the development and growth of the subjectduring the past forty years, would not only be an impossibletask within any reasonable limits but would inevitably destroythe very modest aim which the book sought to achieve. Nosuch attempt will be made here, but this Introduction maywell be concluded by some general remarks concerning thesubsequent fate of the principles which the book describes.

The dominating feature of the history of the first half of thepresent century has been the increasing influence exerted bythe works of Freud. This influence has extended far beyondthe limits of the orthodox psychoanalytical school, and it isnot too much to say that his conceptions have profoundlyaffected the course of nearly all modern psychopathologicalinvestigation. This statement does not mean that there hasbeen a general acceptance of the vast structure of theory andpractice which Freud has erected. On the contrary, the validityof that structure is still a subject of more or less acrimoniousdispute, and Freud's doctrines are embraced in their entiretyonly by a relatively small school of thought composed of hisimmediate followers, and constituting what we have termedthe orthodox school of psychoanalysis. The new avenues ofapproach to psychological problems which Freud first opened,however, the weapons which he devised for his investigations,and the supremely important establishment of a dynamicoutlook in research, all these have fundamentally modified thewhole subsequent history of psychopathology. Moreover, aconsiderable number of Freud's earlier conceptions—inparticular the notion of conflict and the various ' mechanisms'whereby conflict produces the phenomena of neurotic dis-order—have attained a wide recognition, and are indeedwithin a measurable degree of general acceptance.

The orthodox school of psychoanalysis, mainly under thedirect leadership of its founder, has developed the method ofpsychoanalysis into an elaborate and complex weapon ofinvestigation, and has extended its researches into ever-widen-ing fields. In addition to the sphere of nervous disorder, whichwas the subject of Freud's earlier work, normal psychology,

11

Page 25: The Psychology of Insanity

sociology, anthropology, and education have been successivelyattacked. It may indeed be said that the Freudian doctrineshave developed into a more or less complete and self-containedsystem of thought, seeking to solve the problems of life andmind along its own lines, and with but little contact or co-operation with other methods of approach.

In this development Freud's earlier conceptions have beengenerally maintained, but they have sustained an extensiveelaboration. The growth and mutations of the libido have beentraced out in great detail, and the factors formerly groupedroughly together as the 'ego' have been analysed into severalcomponents, each possessing definite characters and functions.In the interaction of these components and those of the libidoan explanation has been sought of the phenomena of normaland morbid mental life, and the explanation has been pushedinto almost every sphere of psychological and biologicalactivity.

It has been pointed out that the influence of Freud's workhas extended far beyond the orthodox school of psychoanalysis,and certain of his conceptions have been incorporated in thework of many other psychopathologists who are not preparedto accept Freud's views in their entirety. Two schools ofthought call for special mention here, founded respectively byJung and Adler. These investigators were formerly followers ofFreud, but their lines of advance have diverged widely fromthe path of orthodox psychoanalysis. Both Jung and Adlerhave availed themselves of the new avenues opened up byFreud and have to some extent adopted certain of his concep-tions, but each has proceeded along a separate road, and hasproduced an almost completely independent body of doctrineand practice.

The divergencies between these two schools, and indeedthose between all the various competing schools of psycho-pathology at the present day, are essentially dependent uponthe seeking of deeper concepts than those relatively simpleand superficial ones to which this book is mainly confined, andthe latter therefore have not been very materially affected.

12

Page 26: The Psychology of Insanity

It may be remarked that the divergencies which seem in-evitably to occur when an attempt is made to formulatedeeper concepts are a characteristic illustration of a funda-mental weakness of the psychological method of approach incomparison with that employed by other sciences, notablyphysics. In chapter n it is explained that the method ofscience consists in three steps, firstly the collection andrecording of phenomena, secondly the classification of thesephenomena into series or sequences, and thirdly the discoveryof a short formula which will enable us to describe thesesequences in the most comprehensive and convenient manner.This third step not only provides a formula which permits ofthe facts observed being resumed, but it should also permitof our predicting other sequences of phenomena, particularlythose resulting from controlled experiments. It is in the attemptto fulfil the third step completely that the relative weakness ofthe psychological conception appears. In physics no theoreticalconstruction would be accepted as valid unless it served notonly to resume the facts observed, but also enabled us to pre-dict without failure the course of other sequences experi-mentally controlled. Now psychological theories can be con-structed to resume or explain observed facts, but it is rarelypossible, except in the case of comparatively simple processes,to carry out that decisive part of the third step, the predictingof the results which will be achieved by experimental investi-gation of further sequences. Hence the ground is left free fordifferent psychopathologists to devise different theoreticalconstructions, which do in fact serve to resume and explainthe phenomena observed, but which are mutually incompat-ible. The conclusive test in deciding between them, namely,their capacity to predict with certainty the course of othersequences of phenomena, particularly of phenomena experi-mentally regulated, is, to a great extent, lacking, at any ratewith regard to the phenomena dealt with in this book. Hencedivergent schools of thought unfortunately but inevitablyarise.

The attack on the problems of mental disorder is nowadays

Page 27: The Psychology of Insanity

being conducted on a very wide front. Apart from theapproaches which stem wholly or in part from the work ofFreud, psychologists are carrying out investigations whichemploy experimental, mathematical, and statistical methods,and which seek to remain strictly within the canons of scien-tific research. The problems of human behaviour, both normaland morbid, are being examined by many authorities with theaid of concepts built differently from those of the analyticalpsychopathologists, and with the help of contributions culledfrom such ancillary sciences as sociology and anthropology.

Finally there have been great developments within what isdescribed in chapter n as the 'physiological conception', i.e.the view that mental phenomena are manifestations of pro-cesses taking place in the brain and other organs, with theresultant corollary that the search for fundamental causesmust be directed to those physical processes. These develop-ments have not so far resulted in demonstrating satisfactorilythe anatomical, physiological and chemical changes whichunderlie the phenomena of insanity, though some progresshas been made in this direction, but lie in the field of treat-ment. In recent years direct attack upon the brain by electricaland operative measures has proved remarkably fruitful indealing with certain disorders. It is not unreasonable to sup-pose that, when the physiological and other changes respon-sible for these results have been discovered, they will fallwithin a physiological rather than a psychological conception.

Page 28: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER I

THE HISTORY OF MENTAL DISORDER

R E C O R D S of abnormal mental phenomena reach back to thevery dawn of history, and are to be found in the oldest booksin both the Eastern and the Western world. Thus, in the OldTestament we read of Saul's recurring periods of depression,when 'the evil spirit from the Lord' was upon him. We read,again, of the delirium of Nebuchadnezzar, in which he be-lieved himself changed into an animal—he ' did eat grass likean ox, and his body was wet with the dew of heaven, till hishairs grew like the feathers of eagles, and his nails like birds'claws'. To turn to the West, abnormal mental phenomenafrequently appear in the pages of Homer. Ajax was torturedby the Furies till he fell upon his own sword, and we are toldthat Ulysses simulated madness in order to justify his abstentionfrom the Trojan war. The famous oracles are not altogetherattributable to fraud, but are probably partly to be explainedas hysterical manifestations similar to those found in theMedium' of the present day.

Side by side with the abnormal phenomenon we invariablyfind its attempted explanation, because the demand forexplanation is a fundamental character of the human mind.Throughout the history of mental disorder, and particularlywith regard to the more severe forms of mental disordercomprised under the term * insanity', this demand constantlymakes itself felt, endeavouring to obtain satisfaction by theconstruction of explanations in harmony with the generalthought and knowledge of the period. These attemptedexplanations we shall know as the various 'conceptions ofmental disorder', and the aim of the present chapter will be totrace their historical development until we reach the modern'psychological conception of mental disorder', with whichthis book as a whole is mainly concerned.

Page 29: The Psychology of Insanity

Now the conception of mental disorder to be found in thoseancient records mentioned above may be described as the' demonological \ The phenomena were regarded as the mani-festations of some spiritual being, god or demon, who eitheractually inhabited the body of his victim, or who merelyplayed upon him from without. If the phenomena manifestedwere in harmony with the religious views of the time it wasconcluded that the controlling spirit was benign in character,and the individual possessed was revered as an exceptionallyholy person. If, on the other hand, the individual's conductconflicted with the dominating ethical code, he was thought tobe the victim of a malignant devil. So long as this view wasgenerally accepted, it was natural that the only curative treat-ment in force was the employment of religious ceremonialsand incantations.

With the coming of Hippocrates, however, somewhere aboutthe year 460 B.C., the conception of insanity in Greece under-went a radical change. Hippocrates, the father of medicine,laid down the principle that the brain was the organ of mind,and that insanity was merely the result of some disturbance inthis organ. He £led his patients out of the temple of iEscialapiusand proceeded to treat them along the lines of ordinarymedicine'.

This view, the first attempt to attack insanity by the methodof science, was not destined at that time to any very fruitfuldevelopment, and it disappeared altogether in the intellectualstagnation of the Dark Ages. Medieval Europe shows us thesubordination of thought, literature, and art to the service of anall-powerful church, the replacement of philosophy by scho-lasticism, and of science by mysticism.

The prevailing views upon the nature and causation ofinsanity reverted, as a natural consequence, to the demono-logical conception of the ancients. The doctrine that abnormalmental symptoms were the product of a supernatural agency,holy or evil, again made its appearance, and attained in theMiddle Ages to its extreme development.

In the records of the ascetics and ecstatics who flourished at16

Page 30: The Psychology of Insanity

that period we find manifestations constantly described,visions and trances for example, which are of frequent occur-rence in the mentally disordered patient of today. The currentbeliefs of the Middle Ages, however, regarded such phenomenaas the result of an intimate communion with the Deity, and theindividuals in whom they occurred were correspondinglyrevered and esteemed.

A number of other abnormal mental phenomena weregrouped together under the conception of'witchcraft', one ofthe most characteristic products of medieval thought. The ageof witchcraft presents a fascinating chapter of human history,still replete with unsolved problems. It is very probable, how-ever, that many of the rites of witchcraft, the witches' sabbathand other feasts, were relics of the prehistoric religion ofEurope, the religion of German mythology. They thereforeformed, as it were, a cult persisting alongside the dominatingreligion of the day. Now cults of this character inevitablyattract to their ranks numerous recruits from the army of thementally unstable, a fact which we can see constantly exempli-fied in our own time. Hence it is not surprising that we findamongst the witches numbers of people who would now bedefinitely classed as neurotic or insane. Certain signs which arewell known to the modern physician as symptoms of hysteriabecame, indeed, regarded as indisputable proofs that aparticular individual was a witch. One such sign was thefamous 'devil's claw', a patch of insensitive skin somewhereupon the body of the alleged witch, a sign frequently met within the modern hospital under the less lurid name of' hystericalanaesthesia'. The determination of the existence of the 'devil'sclaw', together with a number of other fantastic tests, consti-tuted the procedure of the witch-trial. This atrocious institu-tion obtained a firm hold upon the nations of Europe, andpersisted even into the eighteenth century. Some idea of itsextent may be gained from the fact that within a few yearssix thousand five hundred people were executed for witchcraftin the principality of Treves alone.

Those abnormal mental phenomena which could be

Page 31: The Psychology of Insanity

ascribed neither to holiness nor to witchcraft were mostlythought to be due to the agency of malignant demons. Theunfortunate individuals who exhibited them were subjectedto exorcism and other ceremonials and, if this treatment failedto produce a cure, they were cast into dungeons, or ostracisedfrom society.

The reform of this very unsatisfactory state of affairs wasdue to the development of two distinct lines of thought—science and humanitarianism. The method of science, whichwas soon to revolutionise human knowledge, was in its earlydays almost solely devoted to the study of the material world.The objective mode of thought which this study induced,however, could not but have far-reaching effects, and with thedecay of scholasticism came the decay of the demonologicalconception of insanity. Finally, modern Europe attained tothat stage which Hippocrates had reached more than a thou-sand years before. Mental phenomena were thought to bemanifestations of processes taking place in the brain, and theprinciple was laid down that insanity was a disease of the brain,just as pneumonia was a disease of the lungs. At the beginningof the nineteenth century, therefore, we find the modern4 physiological conception' of insanity definitely established.

This stage was preceded by a transition period dominatedby what may be termed the 'political conception'. Althoughthe insane were no longer regarded as the peculiar propertyof the devil, it was thought that they had no claim upon theconsideration of society. So long as the madman was preventedfrom troubling his fellow-men, the community felt that everyduty had been discharged. This was the epoch of dungeonsand chains.

Men covered with filth cowered in cells of stone, cold, damp,without air or light, and furnished with a straw bed that wasrarely renewed, and which soon became infectious—frightfuldens where we should scruple to lodge the vilest animals. Theinsane thrown into these receptacles were at the mercy of theirattendants, and these attendants were convicts from prison.The unhappy patients were loaded with chains and bound likegalley slaves.

18

Page 32: The Psychology of Insanity

The revolting misery of the asylums of those days has beenpictured by the hand of Hogarth; it can hardly be describedin words.

The first work of humanitarianism in the field of insanitystands to the credit of England. In the reform of St Luke's inLondon, towards the end of the eighteenth century, and thefoundation of the Retreat in York, we meet with the firstserious attempt to better the material circumstances of theinsane. Dr Gonolly at Hanwell abolished the chains whichhad been hitherto an essential feature of every asylum, andsimilar reforms were carried out in France under the leader-ship of Pinel and Esquirol. Since those days the humanitarianmovement has made continuous progress, the right of the insaneto be treated as human beings is now universally recognised,and the mental hospital of today has become a model ofcomfort and orderliness.

This advance in the methods of administration and treat-ment has been helped at every step by the parallel advance ofscience. By the end of the eighteenth century the view thatabnormal mental phenomena must be attacked along the lineswhich had everywhere else led to a material advance in know-ledge had attained a firm hold, and at that period the founda-tions were laid of a genuine scientific study of insanity. Thisstudy, constituting the branch of science known as psychiatry,has undergone a great development during the past hundredyears, and a considerable body of knowledge has now beenaccumulated.

We have seen that at the beginning of the nineteenthcentury, the physiological conception had attained almostuniversal acceptance. Research began to be devoted mainlyto the anatomy and physiology of the brain, and our know-ledge of these subjects increased at an extraordinarily rapidrate. With the aid-of the microscope the anatomical structureof the brain was worked out in its most minute details, and theapplication of experimental methods to cerebral physiologyled to still further advances. Chief amongst the latter wasthe demonstration of the facts of cerebral topography, the

19

Page 33: The Psychology of Insanity

discovery that definite portions of the brain controlled definitebodily functions. It was found, for example, that a portionof the brain, now known as the * motor area', controlled all themovements of the head and limbs, so that if a part of this areawere destroyed, complete paralysis of the corresponding limbimmediately followed.

In the enthusiasm created by these discoveries it was con-fidently anticipated that the nature and causes of mentaldisorder would speedily be laid bare. These hopes have notbeen realised, however, and the opinion is rapidly gainingground that, although the value of the physiological methodcannot be disputed, there is ample room for some other modeof approaching the problem. This other mode has now beenfurnished by the development of the 'psychological conception'.

The psychological conception is based on the view thatmental processes can be directly studied without any referenceto the accompanying changes which are presumed to takeplace in the brain, and that mental disorder may therefore beproperly attacked from the standpoint of psychology. Earlyattempts to develop this aspect were largely vitiated by theconfusion of psychology with metaphysics, theology, andethics. We find, for example, Heinroth maintaining that in-sanity was the result of sin, and could only be cured by theattainment of religious faith. Finally, however, psychologysucceeded in freeing itself from its alien companions, and theway was clear for its application to the study of mentaldisorder. The first great advances in this direction weremade by the French psychologists during the latter half ofthe nineteenth century, culminating in the classical work ofJanet. In recent years progress has been rapid, and with theresearches of Kraepelin, Freud, and Jung, the psychologicalconception of mental disorder has become a recognised avenueof explanation and attack.

At the present day, therefore, there are two dominating'conceptions', the physiological and the psychological, differ-ing widely in their mode of dealing with the subject, but bothalike founded upon the employment of the scientific method.

20

Page 34: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER II

THE PSYCHOLOGICAL CONCEPTION OF

MENTAL DISORDER

IT is necessary that we should clearly understand what ismeant by the psychological conception of mental disorder, therelation it bears to the physiological conception, and the natureof its aims and methods. The consideration of these problemsinvolves some preliminary acquaintance with the fundamentalpropositions upon which modern science is based, and in-evitably leads to questions which are, strictly speaking, beyondthe limits of our subject. But as no clear thinking in psychologyis possible unless precise notions about these elementarymatters have been previously acquired, we may perhaps bepardoned for temporarily trespassing upon the domain ofphilosophy.

It has been pointed out that modern science is attacking theproblem of mental disorder along two different routes. Thepsychological conception treats the phenomena as states ofmind, whereas the physiological conception treats them merelyas manifestations of changes occurring in the brain. Now inthis statement we are confronted with certain terms which,although loosely and erroneously used in ordinary language,have nevertheless a precise and definite signification. Theseterms are 'science', 'mind5, 'brain', 'physiology', and'psychology'.

Everybody is aware that science is a method of acquiringknowledge, but everybody is not aware that this method isalways one and the same, whatever the subject may be towhich it is being applied. The scientist who devotes himself topsychology proceeds in exactly the same manner as the scien-tist who devotes himself to chemistry. The universal methodof science consists in certain definite steps, and its nature

21

Page 35: The Psychology of Insanity

will be best understood by the consideration of a simpleexample.1

Let us take the process by which we have attained our know-ledge of the motion of the planetary system. In the earlier daysof astronomy efforts were made to explain this motion by theinvention of numerous fantastic hypotheses, but with the ad-vent of Copernicus, Tycho Brahe, and Kepler, these hypotheseswere abandoned, and the problem was attacked by the slowbut sure method of science. The first step was the laboriouscollection of the necessary facts. The position of a certain planetin the heavens was carefully observed on a certain day, and theobservation repeated at intervals on various subsequent days.These observations were duly classified and in this way arecord of the successive positions occupied by the planetduring its course was finally obtained. The next step was thediscovery of a convenient formula by which these successivepositions could be shortly and adequately described. It wasdiscovered by Kepler that if we assume each planet to movearound the sun in a certain curve, known to mathematiciansas an ellipse, it will be found that our assumption is in preciseagreement with the previously collected facts. Thus, knowingthe planet's position on i January, and knowing its rate ofmotion, we could calculate how far it would have moved alongthe ellipse by 14 January. If we then turned to our recordedobservation of the planet's position on 14 January, we shouldfind that the calculated position and the position determinedby actual observation were in precise agreement. As this testis invariably satisfied, Kepler's formula has been admittedto the rank of a scientific law.

If we analyse the procedure by which this law was ultimatelyreached, we find that it consists of three successive steps : (1) thecollection and recording of facts; (2) the classification of thesefacts into series or sequences; (3) the discovery of a shortformula, or (scientific law', which will enable us to describethese sequences of facts in the most comprehensive and con-

1 For the conception of the method of science developed in this chapterthe author is mainly indebted to Prof. Karl Pearson's Grammar of Science.

22

Page 36: The Psychology of Insanity

venient manner. This is the method of science, and whateverthe subject may be, it is the sole method which science everemploys.

Let us now examine another example of the scientificmethod, the discovery of the various laws constituting the earlyhistory of the atomic theory. It is at once clear that the chemisthas proceeded by the same three steps which we found in thecase of Kepler's planetary law. Firstly the ascertaining of thefacts, represented here by the observation of chemical sub-stances, and of the manner in which they decompose or com-bine together in bulk. Secondly the classification of the factsinto series, whereby it is found that in this decomposition andcombination the proportion of the constituent substances isalways the same. Thirdly the construction of a scientific lawdesigned to explain these facts. This third step was carried outby Dalton; he conceived the hypothesis that chemical sub-stances are composed of minute elements or 'atoms', and thatthese atoms combine together according to certain simpleprinciples. He found that the formulae thus obtained, con-stituting in their totality the well-known 'atomic theory',enabled him not only to explain all the facts of chemicalcombination and decomposition which had already beenascertained by experiment, but also to predict what wouldhappen in any further experiments of a similar kind. Dalton'stheory has been subjected to innumerable tests, and it hasbeen found always to agree with the facts of experience. Theformulae composing it are therefore, like Kepler's ellipses,now regarded as established scientific laws. The theory is,indeed, so universally recognised and taught, it is so immenselyuseful, and it explains so much, that the lay reader is in dangerof falling into error concerning its true character.

Although Kepler's ellipses and Dalton's atomic theory haveboth been attained by the use of the scientific method, yetthere is an important distinction between them. In the secondexample a new factor has appeared; we find that Dalton notonly constructed a scientific law, but invented the objectsbetween which the law is conceived to hold. He did not know

23

Page 37: The Psychology of Insanity

that atoms had any real existence at all. Atoms were merelyconstructions of the scientific imagination. Precisely similarstatements apply to the wave theory of light; the ether and itswaves had never been actually observed, they were inventedby the scientist in order to explain the facts of light and heat.But their actual non-existence did not in the least vitiatethe value which they had for science. They enabled us toresume and predict a vast number of facts, and this is the solejustification which scientific law is ever required to possess.

The distinction which underlies these remarks is expressedin the terms 'phenomenal* and * conceptual'. 'Phenomena'are facts of experience, things which can be actually observed.'Concepts' are inventions of the scientist, designed to resume,or in other words, to explain the facts of experience. For exam-ple, chemical substances and coloured objects are phenomena,atoms and ether waves are concepts.

We are now in a position to complete our description of themethod of science. It consists in (i) the observation andrecording of the phenomena; (2) the classification of therecorded phenomena into groups or series; (3) the discovery ofa formula which will enable us to resume these series in themost comprehensive and convenient manner. The formulamay be altogether conceptual in character, that is to say, itmay avail itself of imaginary objects whose real existence innature cannot be demonstrated. The only test which it isrequired to satisfy is the test of utility, it must explain the factswhich we actually find, and it must enable us to predict theoccurrence of future facts. If, then, the study of mental disorderis to be made worthy of the name of science, this is the methodwhich must be employed, and the broad lines of the task beforeus are now clear. A further difficulty, however, remains to besolved. If there is but one method of research, what is thedistinction between the physiological conception and thepsychological conception?

The physiological conception admits that the phenomena ofmental disorder are phenomena of consciousness, but itassumes that the mental processes are accompanied by corre-

24

Page 38: The Psychology of Insanity

sponding changes in the brain, and to these brain changes itdevotes all its attention. With the phenomena as facts of con-sciousness it has no immediate concern. The first aim of thephysiological conception is to find the actual changes in thebrain which occur in mental disorder and the brain changescorrelated with each morbid mental process. Its ultimate aimis the discovery of convenient ' laws' which will describe thesebrain processes in the shortest and most comprehensivemanner. These laws will, of course, contain nothing butphysiological terms—terms of consciousness will find no placetherein.

The psychological conception, on the other hand, takesfrom the outset an altogether different route. It regards theconscious processes occurring in mental disorder as the actualphenomena with which it is called upon to deal. Its ultimateaim is the discovery of convenient ' laws' which will shortlyand comprehensively describe these conscious processes. In thiscase the laws will contain nothing but psychological terms—terms of brain will find no place therein.

It is of the utmost importance that, in the final claws'obtained by either the physiological or the psychological con-ception, there should be no mixing of the terms. The physio-logical laws must contain no psychological terms, and thepsychological laws must contain no physiological terms.Nothing but hopeless confusion can result from the mixtureof * brain-cells' and ' ideas'. The reader must be asked toaccept this statement as a dogma. Any adequate demonstra-tion of its truth would take us far beyond the limits of thisbook.1

The determination of the ultimate relation which the1 This rigid avoidance of a mixture of * brain-cells' and * ideas* only applies

to conceptual explanations, i.e. to the third step of the method of * science.'There is no objection to conjoining both types in earlier stages where onlya recording of a succession of phenomena is attempted, e.g. the statementthat excessive ingestion of alcohol produces mental confusion. For a moredetailed consideration of the nature of the physiological and psychologicalconceptions and of their relationship see the author's Psychopathology(Macmillan Company, 1927).

25

Page 39: The Psychology of Insanity

physiological and psychological conceptions bear to oneanother involves the much disputed question of the connectionbetween mind and brain, and belongs to philosophy. It can-not of course, be entered upon here. From the point of viewof science, a clear understanding of the simple distinctiondescribed above is all that is necessary.

An endeavour has been made to arrange the subject-matterof the book in such a way that the three successive steps of themethod of science will appear in their logical order. Chapterin describes the phenomena of mental disorder, the facts whichwe observe in our patients. In chapter iv these facts are col-lected into groups, arranged, and classified. We then proceedin chapter v and other subsequent chapters to the explanationof these facts, the various psychological laws which resume thephenomena observed. The reader is here introduced to con-ceptual psychology, and his understanding of this difficultportion of the subject will be considerably clearer if he hasadequately grasped the distinction between the phenomenaland conceptual outlined above. He will find that, in modernpsychology, conceptions are employed which cannot bedemonstrated to have an actual phenomenal existence.* Complexes' and 'repression', for example, are conceptions de-vised to explain the phenomena which are observed, just asin physical science the concepts of' force ' and £ energy' aredevised to explain the phenomena of motion. He will find,again, such conceptual abstractions as 'unconscious mentalprocesses', involving the assumption that mental processes existof which the individual himself is absolutely unconscious. Itwill perhaps appear at first sight that the assumption involvesa psychological impossibility, and that if a mental processexists it must, ipso facto, be accompanied by consciousness.The reader must remember, however, that he is dealing witha conception which lays no claim to phenomenal reality, andthat it belongs to the same generic type as the ether of thephysicist.1 An unconscious mental process is a phenomenal

1 The view that unconscious mental processes are conceptual constructionsis not accepted by the psychoanalytical school. This school maintains that

26

Page 40: The Psychology of Insanity

impossibility just as the weightless frictionless ether is a pheno-menal impossibility. In both cases the conception justifiesits claim to rank as a scientific theory, because it serves toresume and explain in a comprehensive and convenientmanner the facts of our experience, and because it satisfiesthe one great criterion of science, the test of utility.

unconscious mental processes are inferred in the same way that the con-scious processes of others are inferred and hence possess the same claim tophenomenal reality. For a fuller discussion of this point see Psychopathology(Macmillan Company, 1927), pp. 57 ff.

Page 41: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER III

THE PHENOMENA OF MENTAL

DISORDER

T H E task which lies before us is to explain how the psycho-logical conception maybe applied to the phenomena of mentaldisorder, and to show that those phenomena are the result ofdefinite psychological causes operating in accordance withdefinite psychological laws.

At the outset we encounter an obstacle which, though notperhaps peculiar to the subject we have chosen, offers excep-tional difficulties on account of the conditions under which thesubject has to be presented. We have to assume that ourreaders are ignorant, not only of the laws which govern thephenomena of mental disorder, but to a considerable extentof those phenomena themselves. Most readers will have someacquaintance with symptoms occurring in the minor forms ofmental disorder known as 'neuroses', but few laymen have anypractical experience of those occurring in the more pro-nounced forms of mental disorder included under 'insanity'.The conception of the insane patient possessed by the publicat large is exaggerated and inaccurate. Hence before we canproceed to the explanation of the symptoms which the insanepatient exhibits, it is necessary that this erroneous conceptionshould be corrected, and we must ensure that our readershave at any rate a superficial acquaintance with the pheno-mena which actually occur. It is to this preliminary task thatthe present chapter is devoted.

To describe in a complete and systematic manner the symp-toms met with in the manifold varieties of insanity is obviouslyimpossible within the limits of a small book. We must be con-tent to concentrate our attention upon a certain number ofthe more prominent manifestations which are apparent to anyobserver who visits the wards of a mental hospital. Our

28

Page 42: The Psychology of Insanity

description will be far from exhaustive, and but little attemptwill be made to achieve order or systematic grouping. Theresult will probably be comparable to the confused impressionwhich the visitor we have imagined will carry away with him,but it will suffice to acquaint the reader with some of the actualfacts of insanity, and with the technical terms which areemployed to describe them. It is hoped, moreover, that thisconfused impression will be gradually removed in laterchapters, and replaced by a more orderly picture in whicheach symptom will acquire its proper setting.

We shall commence with the description of certain generalchanges which may be regarded as affecting the mind as awhole, and then proceed to the enumeration of individualsymptoms, selected either on account of the frequency of theiroccurrence, or because of their peculiarly striking character.It must be clearly understood that the phenomena we shalldescribe are in no sense mutually exclusive, and that many ofthem may occur together in one and the same case.

The first of the general changes we shall describe consistsin a quantitative mental defect, a diminution in the generalmental capacity involving all the functions of the mind. Thepatient cannot think, act, or remember efficiently, his intelli-gence is markedly below the average, and he seems abnor-mally stupid. This quantitative defect occurs in twa forms,the congenital and the acquired, which are known respectivelyas mental deficiency and dementia.

In mental deficiency the patient is born without a normalmental equipment, and the mental powers never attain theirfull development. This failure of development may be of allpossible grades, ranging from an almost complete absence ofthe mind to conditions in which intelligence is only slightlybelow the average. Patients of the lowest grades never progressbeyond the mental status of an infant, they are incapable ofspeech or of the simplest adaptation to their environment,and require all their lives the care and attention customarilydevoted to a baby. Others acquire speech, but cannot learn toread or write. Others, again, develop beyond this stage, but

29

Page 43: The Psychology of Insanity

their knowledge remains very elementary, they never acquireany general ideas, and they are incapable of earning a livingwage or of taking their place as citizens. Mental deficiency isgenerally correlated with an easily demonstrable failure ofbrain development.

In dementia the general defect of mental capacity is ac-quired. The patients have at one time possessed a normalmental equipment, but this has undergone a process of decay.The prototype of this process is the gradual failure of intelli-gence which occurs in normal old age, and some of the bestexamples of dementia may be seen in those cases where themental decay of old age attains an extreme grade. Such casesare termed senile dementia, and are well described in Shake-speare's lines:

Last scene of all,That ends this strange eventful history,Is second childishness and mere oblivion,Sans teeth, sans eyes, sans taste, sans everything.

But a similar quantitative loss may occur at any age, andmay be of any degree, ranging from a simple blunting ofmental acuity to a profound dementia in which the patient isincapable of the simplest mental operation. These acquireddementias are, like mental deficiency, generally correlatedwith marked changes in the brain.

In another variety of general mental change observed incases of insanity, the alteration is qualitative rather thanquantitative. It may be regarded as a change in the generalattitude of the mind towards its experience, either transitory ormore or less permanent. Under this heading are includedexcitement, depression, and apathy.

Everyone is acquainted with the meaning of excitement,and the term does not require further definition. It is a symp-tom of frequent occurrence in insanity, where it differs fromthe similar phenomenon met with in normal mental life mainlyin the exaggeration of its manifestation, in the apparent lackof an adequate cause, and in the fact that it is out of harmony

30

Page 44: The Psychology of Insanity

with the patient's real condition and circumstances. Excite-ment as a symptom of insanity appears in many forms, differ-ing from one another in almost every feature, except in thefundamental fact that the mind is exhibiting an abnormaloutput of energy. One of the commonest forms is known asmanic excitement, a variety which will be best illustrated bythe description of an actual case.

The patient is in a state of constant activity, commencing anew occupation at every moment, and immediately abandon-ing it in favour of another. He is never still, but exhibitsa continual press of activity. He talks rapidly and withoutintermission, flying from one subject to another, with but littlelogical connection. He seems incapable of carrying out anyconnected train of thought, his attention is caught by everytrifling object, and as soon diverted again. He is, generally,abnormally cheerful and absurdly pleased with himself and hisenvironment, though his mood is as mutable as his attention,and changes to anger at the smallest provocation.

Under certain circumstances we might be disposed to regardsuch behaviour as pardonable, though exaggerated and ill-balanced. When, however, we discover that the patient isemaciated and in wretched health, that he has recently under-gone a series of terrible stresses, that the fortunes of himselfand his family are at their lowest ebb, and that now the crown-ing misfortune of removal to a mental hospital has befallenhim, then his present behaviour becomes altogether incompre-hensible. It is so out of harmony with the actual facts of hisposition, that we have no hesitation in regarding his conductas definitely insane.

In other varieties the excitement is more extreme, thecheerfulness is, perhaps, suddenly replaced by bouts of furiousanger, the patient attacks all those about him, is altogetherimpervious to reason and to argument, and presents a pictureapproximating to the popular conception of the maniac.

Depression may be regarded as the converse of excitement.The patient is slow in all his actions, thinks with difficulty, andis miserable and unhappy.

31

Page 45: The Psychology of Insanity

In the third qualitative general change, apathy, the patient isneither excited nor depressed, but absolutely indifferent, andwithout apparent interests, desires, or ambitions. Apathy isbest exemplified in the so-called emotional dementia whichcharacterises many of the chronic patients who constitute thepermanent population of the hospital. The patient sits in acorner of the ward with expressionless face and head hangingdown, making no attempt to occupy himself in any way,evincing no interest in anything that goes on around him, andapparently noticing nothing. If we address him, we obtain noanswer, or perhaps at the best a monosyllabic reply, oftenquite irrelevant to the question asked.

At first sight such a case would seem to present a genuinedementia, an actual quantitative loss of mental capacity of thetype described earlier in this chapter. If, however, we succeedin obtaining an insight into the patient's mind, we find thatthe dementia is largely only apparent; the patient can observe,remember, and carry out complicated trains of thought, if onlywe can provide him with the necessary stimulus. The explana-tion of the condition lies in the profound emotional apathypresent. The patient is completely inert, and makes no use ofhis mental faculties, because he has no interests or desires.The whole external world resembles for him those innumerabletrivial things which we pass by without attention or notice atevery moment of our lives—an object unworthy of theexpenditure of any mental energy.

In the less pronounced forms of emotional dementia thepatients will answer our questions, and perhaps carry outroutine tasks with machine-like regularity. But they evince nointerests, they have no hopes, plans, or ambitions, and theyare content to remain permanently in the narrow world of thehospital.

In addition to the general changes so far described thereoccur in mental disorder a vast number of individual symptomsof the most varied kinds. We shall now proceed to enumeratesome of these symptoms, selected in haphazard fashion, andwithout attempt at classification or coherent order.

32

Page 46: The Psychology of Insanity

The first symptom which we shall select for description is'somnambulism'. This phenomenon, which is more commonlymet with in those so-called ' neurotic' cases belonging to the ill-defined borderland between sanity and insanity, may beexemplified by an account of the case described by Prof. Janetunder the name of 'Irene' .

Irene had nursed her mother through a prolonged illnessculminating in death. The circumstances connected with thedeath were peculiarly painful, and the event produced aprofound shock upon the patient's mind. An abnormal mentalcondition developed, characterised by the frequent appear-ance of symptoms resembling those exhibited by the ordinarysleep-walker. Irene, perhaps engaged at the moment in sewingor in conversation, would suddenly cease her occupation, andwould commence to live over again the scene of her mother'sdeath, carrying out every detail with all the power of anaccomplished actress. While this drama was in progress shewas perfectly unconscious of the actual events happening inher environment, heard nothing that was said to her, and sawnothing but the imaginary scene in which she was living at themoment. This phenomenon, technically termed a somnam-bulism, would end as suddenly as it had begun, and Irene wouldreturn to her former occupation, absolutely unaware of thefact that it had ever been interrupted. After an interval ofperhaps several days a second somnambulism, resembling thefirst in all respects, would appear in the same abrupt manner.If the patient were interrogated during the apparently normalintervals it would be found not only that she had entirely for-gotten everything which had happened during the somnam-bulism, but that the whole system of ideas connected with hermother's death had completely disappeared from her mind.She remembered nothing of the illness or its tragic end;discussed her mother without emotion, and was reproached byher relatives for her callous indifference to the whole subject.This curious localised loss of memory or amnesia will be morefully discussed in a subsequent chapter, when its precise natureand causation will be explained.

33

Page 47: The Psychology of Insanity

The next group of symptoms to which we may direct ourattention comprises hallucinations and delusions. These pheno-mena occupy an important place amongst the manifestations ofinsanity, and may be observed in a large percentage ofpatients.

Hallucinations may be roughly defined as false sense-impres-sions. For example, the patient sees an object which has no realexistence, or hears an imaginary voice. Hallucinations aretermed visual, auditory, tactile, etc., according to the sense towhich the false impression appears to belong. Auditory hallu-cinations are particularly common. The 'voices' may makeremarks of either a pleasant or an unpleasant character, butgenerally they refer to subjects closely related to the patient'smost intimate life, and often they consist of some abusivecomment or reproach reiterated with stereotyped persistence.Thus a patient may hear a voice constantly announcing thaton account of the sins he has committed he will shortly be putto death. Frequently, in order to explain these strangephenomena, the patient constructs some fantastic hypothesis,and persuades himself, for example, that they are producedby 'wireless telephones' or 'spiritualism'.

Delusions are closely allied to hallucinations, and generallyaccompany the latter. The distinction lies in the fact thatdelusions are not false sensations, but false beliefs. Thus if apatient sees an object which has no objective reality he has anhallucination, but if he believes that he is the Emperor of theWorld he has a delusion. Delusions may be of all kinds, butthere are two groups which call for special mention on accountof their great frequency, grandiose and persecutory. In the formerthe patient believes himself to be some exalted personage, orto possess some other attribute which raises him far above thelevel of his fellows. He may believe, for example, that he is theking, or a millionaire, or a great inventor. In some cases noactual delusions are expressed, but the exaggerated sense ofself-importance is betrayed by affectations of gait and manner,by the employment of a fantastically pedantic phraseology, orby other similar manifestations.

34

Page 48: The Psychology of Insanity

A patient who exhibits the second, or persecutory, type ofdelusion believes that deliberate attempts are made to harmhim in some way. Thus he may believe that certain peopleare plotting to destroy his life. Both grandiose and persecutorydelusions are often associated with hallucinations; voices hailthe patient as the rightful owner of the throne, or cover himwith abuse and threaten some dire fate. The two types arefrequently combined; for example, a patient may maintainthat he is the king, but that an organised conspiracy exists todeprive him of his birthright. In this way delusions are some-times elaborated into an extraordinarily complicated system,and every fact of the patient's experience is distorted until it iscapable of taking its place in the delusional scheme.

An important variety of persecutory false belief is consti-tuted by the so-called 'delusions of reference'. The patientmisconstrues every event which happens in his environment,however trivial it may be, believes that it is directly bound upwith his fate, and that it is in some way designed to injure him.If he observes two of his fellows talking together he immediatelyassumes that he is the subject of their conversation, and everyaccidental misfortune is regarded as a deliberate attempt toannoy him. Sometimes this misconstruction is carried tolengths which are fantastically absurd; a trifling displacementof the furniture of the patient's room is thought to be a signalemployed by his enemies, and a spot upon his dinner plate isproof positive that poison is being introduced into his food.

The most striking feature of a delusion is its fixity andimperviousness to all opposing argument. Persuasion andreason are altogether ineffectual against it, and the patientpreserves his belief in spite of the most convincing demonstra-tion of its falsity.

The extent to which conduct is affected by the presence ofdelusions is, however, very variable. In some cases patientsunder the influence of persecutory ideas will commit seriousassaults upon their imagined enemies, and become a sourceof great danger to the community. In a very large number ofcases, on the other hand, the delusion seems to have no direct

35

Page 49: The Psychology of Insanity

effect upon the patient's behaviour. Often, indeed, belief andconduct are completely divorced from one another, or evengrotesquely inconsistent. Thus, the ' Queen of the World' willcontentedly carry out her daily task of scrubbing the wardfloor, and the omnipotent millionaire will beg plaintively fora small gift of tobacco.

We may next proceed to consider the group of phenomenaincluded under the term obsession, which bear a close super-ficial resemblance to delusions, but must be carefully distin-guished therefrom. Obsessions, indeed, rarely occur in actualinsanity, but are a characteristic feature of certain types ofneurotic disorder. An obsession may be defined as the 'over-weighting' of a particular element in consciousness. Thepatient complains of some idea which constantly recurs to hismind in spite of all efforts to banish it, or he is constantlyimpelled to carry out some irrelevant and inappropriateaction. For example, he is haunted by the idea that he issuffering from cancer; he is perfectly aware that no foundationfor this suspicion exists, and that no symptom of the dreadeddisease is actually present. He does not, in fact, really believethat he has cancer, but he cannot banish the idea fromhis mind, and he needs constantly to reassure himself of itserroneous character. It is this absence of a definite false beliefthat constitutes the essential distinction between an obsessionand a delusion.

Or, again, the patient is impelled to carry out repeatedlysome needless and useless action. Thus Freud describes the caseof a lady who had an overwhelming need to examine in themost careful manner the number of every bank-note whichcame into her possession. A not uncommon variety of obsessionis the so-called ' washing mania', in which the patient is drivento wash his hands at almost every moment of the day. He fullyrealises the absurdity of this performance, but the compulsionis irresistible, and all his available time and energy aresquandered in a fruitless struggle to combat the obsession.

We may next direct our attention to a curious phenomenonmost frequently observed in chronic cases of insanity of long

36

Page 50: The Psychology of Insanity

duration, the 'stereotyped action'. The patient carries outsome action with monotonous repetition and regularity dayin and day out. Often all his mental energy is absorbed in thisperformance, so that from one year's end to another he seemsto have no other interest, desire, or ambition. These stereo-typed actions may be of all kinds, and of all degrees of com-plexity, ranging from a simple rhythmical movement of thehands or head to elaborate procedures suggesting the manipu-lations of a skilled tradesman who is plying his craft. Some-times, again, a phrase or sentence is repeated over and overwith the same monotonous persistence. Thus, one of mypatients has for years devoted his entire waking existence toreciting the phrase, ' It's all wrong, I tell you.'

Alterations in speech and phraseology form an importantpart of the symptomatology of insanity. The rapid flow ofdisconnected talk occurring in manic excitement has alreadybeen mentioned. Often, however, the changes observed aremuch more profound. The phrases are curiously distorted,individual words are displaced or omitted, all grammaticalform seems to be lost, and the patient's whole conversation isan incoherent and meaningless hotch-potch. The followingis an excellent example of such incoherent speech: 'Whatspelling letters have you there, do you write it in Greek, doyou write strength, that photography is trouble, ex parte,posse comitatis, I get that, Mr John McCall's stereotypist,physiological design, that's the result on the blue line, it comesup to you on the strength of duty . . . . '

Sometimes an exaggeratedly pedantic phraseology isemployed, in which polysyllabic words are often employedwithout any regard to their precise meaning. One patientcomplains, for example, that his health has been 'deflected',and that he is the victim of * illegal circumstances and cruelconventions'. It will be seen later that such pedantic phraseo-logy is generally employed to emphasise the importance of thepatient or of the statements which he is making, and we havealready observed that it is closely allied to the grandiose delu-sions and affectations of gait and manner dealt with above.

37

Page 51: The Psychology of Insanity

This cursory description of some of the symptoms met within insanity must suffice for the present. Its imperfections havealready been pointed out, and we can hardly hope that thereader will have obtained from it that clear picture of insanitywhich practical acquaintance with patients can alone give.Other symptoms, however, will be described in the courseof subsequent chapters as occasion arises, and the more com-plete accounts of individual cases to be found therein willgive a better understanding of the way in which the variousphenomena are combined together, and of their mode ofdevelopment.

Page 52: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER IV

DISSOCIATION

I N the preceding chapter we have collected together certainof the more prominent phenomena of mental disorder. To theuninitiated eye they appear as a chaos of disconnected facts,each seemingly independent of all the rest. A careful examina-tion will show, however, that there are certain generalattributes common to many of the symptoms displayed by ourpatients. With the aid of these general attributes it is possibleto classify the phenomena into groups, and thereby to reducethe confusion to some sort of order.

Firstly, the conditions described as mental deficiency anddementia may be placed in a separate group. They depend, aswe have seen, upon an absolute quantitative defect of mentalcapacity, and are in this respect fundamentally different fromall the other phenomena dealt with in chapter in. Theseconditions are generally accompanied by a correlated defectin the structure of the brain, and it must be frankly confessedthat, in the present state of knowledge, the psychological con-ception is of relatively little value in the study of their causation,and that the physiological conception is a far more profitableinstrument of investigation. It is true, of course, that psycho-logy is compelled to take account of such quantitative defectsof mental capacity, and that it is able to explain the relationwhich they bear to many of the other phenomena of insanity,but the questions involved are complicated and difficult, andcannot be satisfactorily considered without presupposing aconsiderable practical acquaintance with the subject. Weshall therefore make no attempt to deal further with mentaldeficiency and dementia in this book, but devote all our atten-tion to the qualitative changes in mental function forming thebulk of the phenomena described in the preceding chapter.

We shall at once observe that many of these symptoms are

39

Page 53: The Psychology of Insanity

only exaggerated forms of mental processes with which we areall acquainted. The symptoms described as excitement anddepression, for example, differ from the similar conditions seenin normal men only by their intensity and by their seeminglack of any adequate cause. Similarly, the affective disturbancereferred to as 'emotional dementia' is but an exaggeration ofthe apathy and lack of volition so frequently met with in every-day life.

Other of the affective symptoms, however, seem to befurther removed from the normal—the emotions are not onlyexaggerated, but distorted and senseless. Similarly theincoherent, apparently meaningless phrases exhibited by someof our patients have but little obvious relation to the languageand thought which we find in ourselves. Finally, we meet withsymptoms which seem altogether strange and incomprehen-sible—hallucinations and delusions, for example. Here ouranalogies fail us altogether, and we are tempted to limit ourexplanation to the simple statement that the man is mad, andthat is all there is to say about the matter.

to define true madness,What is't but to be nothing else but mad.

Yet we shall find as we proceed that even the most bizarresymptoms are not so very different from processes to be dis-covered in our own minds, and that the insane patientappears more and more like ourselves the better we are enabledto penetrate into the tortuous recesses of his spirit.

In order that the reader may acquire some of this under-standing, it is necessary that he should be first introducedto a conception which plays an important part throughoutthe whole of abnormal psychology, that of 'dissociation ofconsciousness'.

If we are asked to turn our mental eye inwards and carefullyobserve at any given moment the content of our mind—or, asit is technically termed, the momentary 'field of consciousness'—we should probably describe it as an indivisible whole, auniform stream of thought progressing towards some definite

40

Page 54: The Psychology of Insanity

end. It would not appear to be composed of separate parts,each proceeding independently of the others, but of sensations,ideas, and volitions all united in some common aim. If I amengaged upon a mathematical problem, then my field ofconsciousness seems to consist at the moment solely of thevarious mental processes necessary to the solution of theproblem. A few moments later my attention may perhapsbe diverted to making plans for a forthcoming holiday, butthe mathematical problem will then have temporarily retiredfrom the field of consciousness; the problem and the holidayplans do not both occupy the mind at once, although ourattention may rapidly oscillate from one to the other. Weshould find, moreover, that in spite of the fact that mathe-matics and holidays have apparently nothing in common,there was nevertheless some link which carried my mind overthe gap between them, and that in reality no break in thecontinuity of the stream of thought occurred.

Yet this statement is only partially true of the normal mind,and it is hardly true at all in the case of some of our patients.Their minds are frequently very far from being uniformstreams of thought, progressing towards some definite end,but are on the contrary composed of more or less isolatedmental processes, each pursuing its own development. Thisdivision of the mind into independent fragments, whichare not co-ordinated together to attain some common end,is termed 'dissociation of consciousness5, A few examplesof various degrees of dissociation will make our meaningclear.

It has been pointed out that even the normal mind does notalways present that undivided field of consciousness which wemight be tempted at first sight to ascribe to it. Suppose, forexample, I sit at the piano and play a piece of music. If I ama sufficiently expert performer it is possible that I may at thesame time be able to carry on a complex train of independentthought, let us say the solution of some problem of conduct.My mind does not under these circumstances present a uniformfield of consciousness, but one divided into two parts or

41

Page 55: The Psychology of Insanity

processes. Each of these processes requires a considerableexpenditure of mental energy. The piece of music is perhapsone which I have never seen before, and it has to be playedwith appropriate and constantly varying expression—whilethe problem of conduct may be similarly complicated in itscharacter. Each of these activities is almost entirely inde-pendent of the other, yet both can be carried on at the samemoment. The field of consciousness must therefore be dividedinto two portions, in other words a certain degree of dissocia-tion of consciousness must be present. Similar remarks applyto many other simultaneous activities; for example, thoseexhibited by the skilled tradesman who plies his craft while hismind is at the same time occupied with other matters.

In all these cases, however, the dissociation of consciousnessis temporary, and only partial in character. Both activities areunder the control of the subject, and either may be abandonedat will. In the more marked degrees of dissociation found inour patients this control no longer exists.

Let us take, for example, the phenomenon of 'automaticwriting'. This curious condition, although occasionallyexhibited by comparatively normal people, attains its mostperfect development in the form of disorder known as hysteria.Suppose that we engage an hysterical patient in conversationand, while his attention is thus diverted, insert a pencilbetween the fingers of his right hand. If a third person nowwhispers some question into the patient's ear, it may bepossible to induce him to write answers to those questions,although he continues all the time to discuss with us sometotally different subject. Under such circumstances it will befound that the patient is entirely unconscious of what his handis doing, and is, moreover, often altogether ignorant of theevents which the writing describes. These events frequentlyrelate to episodes in the patient's past life which he appears tohave completely forgotten, and the experiment is occasionallyemployed with the object of resuscitating such buried mem-ories. It may be remarked that this loss of memory for somedefinite section of the patient's past experience, often extending

42

Page 56: The Psychology of Insanity

over a considerable period of time and including events ofgreat importance, is a characteristic symptom of hysteria.

Automatic writing has played a large part in the history ofspiritualism, and has been attributed by supporters of thatdoctrine to the activity of some spiritual being who avails him-self of the patient's hand in order to manifest to the world hisdesires and opinions. So far as the phenomenon itself is con-cerned, however, the explanation is comparatively simple.A dissociation has taken place, though one far more completethan those hitherto described. The field of consciousness isdivided into two distinct parts, one engaged in conversation,the other comprising the systems of ideas which are findingexpression in the automatic writing. Each portion carries oncomplicated mental processes, and yet each is not only inde-pendent of the other, but totally unaware of that other'sexistence. The patient's mind seems, in fact, to be split intotwo smaller minds, engaged in two different occupations,making use of two distinct sets of memories, and without anyrelations whatever one to the other. Such a case, therefore,provides us with a perfect example of dissociation of conscious-ness. But it must always be remembered that, however strangeand incomprehensible such advanced dissociations may atfirst sight seem to be, yet they are nothing but exaggeratedforms of those dissociations which have been seen to occur inevery normal individual.

Let us now proceed to the consideration of a type of dissocia-tion only slightly different from that just described. We foundthat in the uniform stream of thought characteristic of thenormal mind there was no break or gap in the continuity ofideas. However abruptly a new idea might arise in conscious-ness, yet it was always possible to demonstrate that the ap-parent gap was really bridged by some associative link. Theconsciousness of any given moment, moreover, was alwaysperfectly aware of the mental processes which had taken placein the consciousness of the preceding moment. Now it ispossible to imagine that this continuity in the stream of con-sciousness should suddenly cease to exist, that the stream

43

Page 57: The Psychology of Insanity

should be, as it were, suddenly broken across. The content ofconsciousness immediately after the break would then beabsolutely independent of the content of consciousness in themoment preceding the break. All relations between the twowould be severed, and the consciousness of the second momentwould therefore be entirely unaware of what had beencontained in the consciousness of the first moment. The mindof the individual would, in fact, suddenly be filled with a newseries of ideas, while it would at the same time be altogetherignorant of the ideas which had occupied it a moment pre-viously. We have here, not a dissociation of consciousness intotwo separate simultaneously present portions, but a dissocia-tion of the consciousness of one moment from the consciousnesswhich preceded it. This is the type of dissociation which occursin somnambulism. In the case of Irene, described in the lastchapter (p. 33), we saw that at the onset of a somnambulismthe train of thought occupying the patient's mind wasabruptly broken off and replaced by an entirely different setof ideas. Whatever she had previously been engaged upon, thebeginning of the somnambulism was characterised by thesudden invasion into consciousness of the ideas and memoriesconnected with her mother's death. She would live throughthe deathbed scene again and again, her whole mind absorbedin the phantasy, and altogether oblivious of what was actuallytaking place around her. Then suddenly the somnambulismwould cease, and she would 'return to herself. In other words,the train of ideas constituting the somnambulism wouldabruptly disappear from consciousness, and would be replaced,equally abruptly, by the ideas and actions which had occupiedher mind at the moment when the somnambulism commenced.If the patient, after this ' return to herself', were questionedconcerning her recent doings, she would be found to beabsolutely ignorant of everything which had taken placeduring the somnambulism. Her memory would show a gapextending from the exact moment when the somnambulismbegan to the exact moment when it ceased. We should find, infact, that the continuous stream of her thought had been

44

Page 58: The Psychology of Insanity

interrupted by the sudden appearance of a ' dissociated systemof ideas', which occupied the entire field of consciousness fora certain time, and then as suddenly disappeared. In such acase the continuity of transition observed in the normal mindhas been replaced by an abrupt change from one train of ideasto another train which has no relation to the first. If we com-pare the field of consciousness to a cinematograph screen, thenthe normal process corresponds to the continuous change inthe picture produced by a single film, while the dissociatedprocesses occurring in somnambulism correspond to the effectobtained by abruptly breaking off one film, and replacing itby another representing an altogether different subject. Thetype of dissociation seen in automatic writing, on the otherhand, would be produced by employing two films at the samemoment, each projecting its picture upon a separate portionof the same screen.

The dissociated system of ideas whose eruption into the fieldof consciousness is responsible for the appearance of a somnam-bulism, may attain to any degree of complexity and develop-ment. In the case of Irene its structure was relatively simple,and it comprised but little beyond the ideas connected withthe mother's illness and death. Hence, while the somnam-bulism was in progress, the patient's mental life seemednarrowed down to the expression of those ideas; she wastotally insusceptible to all other impressions, and incapable ofadapting herself to the actual conditions of her environment.In some cases, however, the dissociated system is far moreextensive and more completely developed, including withinitself whole tracts of the patient's mental life. Under thesecircumstances the patient's behaviour may be comparativelynormal, and adapted to the environment, even when thedissociated system is in entire possession of the field. Such casesare not generally termed somnambulisms, although they areprecisely similar to the latter in their fundamental characters,but are regarded as examples of * double personality'.

Double personality is a phenomenon which has arousedconsiderable popular interest, owing, no doubt, to the

45

Page 59: The Psychology of Insanity

dramatic character of its manifestations. It has furnishedfascinating material for works of fiction, headed by the famous'Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde' of R. L. Stevenson. A large numberof actual cases, however, have now been described, and in itsless perfect forms double personality is by no means so rare asis generally supposed. As an illustrative example we may quotethe case of the Rev. Ansel Bourne, originally described byWilliam James.

On 17 January 1887, the Rev. Ansel Bourne, an itinerantpreacher, drew a considerable sum of money from a bank inProvidence, and then entered a tram-car. This was the lastincident which he remembered.

He did not return home that day, and nothing was heard ofhim for two months. . . . On the morning of 14 March, how-ever, at Norristown, Pennsylvania, a man calling himself A. J.Brown, who had rented a small shop six weeks previously,stocked it with stationery, confectionery, fruit and smallarticles, and carried on his quiet trade without seeming toanyone unnatural or eccentric, woke up in a fright and calledin the people of the house to tell him where he was. He saidthat his name was Ansel Bourne, that he knew nothing ofshopkeeping, and that the last thing he remembered—itseemed only yesterday—was drawing the money from the bankin Providence.

Now it will at once be apparent that in this case an extensivedissociation had occurred. The normal stream of consciousnesswas suddenly broken across and replaced by a series of alto-gether different mental processes. This new system, sufficientlycomplex in its structure to permit of the patient leading anorderly existence, occupied the stage for two months, whenit disappeared with equal abruptness and the former streamresumed its course. It will be clear that such a case differsfrom a somnambulism only in the more elaborate develop-ment of the systems of ideas concerned.

All the examples of dissociation so far given show us systemsof ideas, or trains of thought, which are split off from the restof consciousness, and which lead an independent existence.

46

Page 60: The Psychology of Insanity

Let us now examine these examples more closely, with a viewto determining what exactly we are to understand by this'splitting off' of a system of ideas. In both automatic writingand somnambulism two well-marked characters are present.Firstly, the main body of consciousness—or, as it is usuallytermed, the personality or ego—has no knowledge of the dis-sociated system. Thus Irene in her normal state had no memoryof the actions and ideas which had rilled the period of somnam-bulism. Secondly, the dissociated system develops autono-mously, that is to say it pursues its own course without anydependence upon the main body of consciousness. It is, in fact,altogether exempt from the control of the personality. Irenecould not decide beforehand what actions should be carried outin her somnambulisms. The ideas connected with her mother'sdeath developed as a self-contained system, over which thepersonality could exercise no influence whatever.

The same characters distinguish the phenomenon of auto-matic writing. Firstly, the patient is quite unaware of what hishand is writing, or even of the fact that it is in movement.Secondly, the personality has no power to direct what thehand shall write, or to alter in any way the train of ideas whichit is expressing.

The question now arises whether both the charactersdescribed are to be regarded as the essential marks of a dis-sociated or ' split off' system of ideas, or whether we may speakof dissociation when only one of these characters is present;and if only one need be present, which is to be regarded asessential—the fact that the personality is unaware of theexistence of the dissociated system, or the fact that the latterdevelops independently and is exempt from the control of theformer.

Now a little consideration will show that all cases whichexhibit the first character must inevitably exhibit the secondalso. If the mind of a certain patient contains a system of ideasof which the personality is absolutely ignorant, then thatsystem must obviously be independent, and exempt from thecontrol of the personality. The first character, therefore,

47

Page 61: The Psychology of Insanity

presupposes the second. It is, in fact, only an extreme degreeof the second. All cases which display it possess not only aseparated, independent, and autonomous system of ideas, butone of whose existence the personality is in addition unaware.We therefore reach the conclusion that ' unawareness' isonly a special example of 'independence', and hence that'independence' is the more fundamental and comprehensivecharacter. It will be found convenient to make the term'dissociation3 indicate only this fundamental character ofindependence, and to regard unawareness on the part of thepersonality merely as a special case of dissociation. We mayexpress this position by the following definition: A system ofideas is said to be dissociated when it is divorced from thepersonality, and when its course and development are exemptfrom the control of the personality.

We are now in a position to proceed further in the examina-tion of our patients, and to determine if there are not othersymptoms than automatic writing, somnambulism, and doublepersonality, which may be brought under this definition ofdissociation. Consider, for example, the case of obsessions. Ifwe inquire of the patient mentioned on p. 36, why she soconscientiously studies the number of every bank-note whichcomes into her possession, she replies, * I do not know why I doso, but I simply cannot help it. Whenever I see a bank-note,something forces me to examine the number. Of course I amdistressed at my foolish behaviour, but the impulse is absolutelyuncontrollable.5 In other words, the sight of a bank-notearouses a system of ideas, whose development the patient'spersonality is altogether unable to control. Whatever she mayherself desire to do, this system will pursue its course until ithas achieved its end, and she will be compelled to look at thenumber. She is, of course, perfectly aware of her action, butcannot alter it or prevent it. We have here a system of ideaswhich is separate from, and develops independently of, thepersonality, and which our definition therefore entitles us todescribe as dissociated. This type of dissociation differs fromthat seen in automatic writing in the fact that the personality

48

Page 62: The Psychology of Insanity

is aware of the existence of the dissociated system. The inde-pendence of the dissociated system is, however, equally evidentin both.

Similar remarks hold good of the various other obsessiveactions, e.g. 'washing mania', which we have observed incertain of our patients.

It should be remarked that phenomena analogous to theselatter symptoms frequently occur in the experience of everynormal individual. For example, the melody which 'runs inone's head' continuously, and will not be banished; the absurdand irrelevant idea which insistently recurs to one's mind indefiance of all the laws of logic; the irresistible impulse to touchevery lamp-post one passes, and so on. In all these cases, just asin those more exaggerated instances which occur in ourpatients, we have dissociated fragments of mind which pursuetheir own course without relation to the conscious aims anddesires of the personality. The personality is aware of theexistence of the dissociated system, but is aware of it as some-thing outside of and foreign to itself. As the patient will fre-quently express it—cthe idea forces itself into my mind','something suddenly compels me to do this action'.

These obsessional cases, in which the dissociated systemappears to the personality as a foreign body which hasintruded itself into the mind, serve as a bridge to carry us overto yet another type of dissociation. Consider the cases describedin the last chapter in which hallucinations of various kindsoccur. We found, for example, a patient who constantly heardvoices announcing that on account of the sins he had com-mitted he would shortly be put to death. Now we know thatthese voices did not correspond to any actual reality in theexternal world. Although to the patient himself they seemedintensely real, to the bystander they were nothing but figmentsof the imagination. In other words, they existed only in thepatient's mind, and were, in fact, merely a portion of his ownconsciousness. But, although the voices formed a part of themind, yet it is obvious that they did not form a part of the per-sonality. It will hence be evident that the voices, and the

49

Page 63: The Psychology of Insanity

system of ideas which the voices express, are to be regardedas dissociated portions of the patient's own consciousness.Strictly speaking, it would be better to say that the system ofideas in question is dissociated from the personality, and thatthe hallucinatory 'voice5 is the mode in which the dissociatedsystem announces its existence to the personality. This splittingof the patient's consciousness into two parts, one of whichtalks to the other, is a frequent phenomenon in every mentalhospital.

The conception of dissociation enables us, again, to repre-sent more clearly to ourselves the mental state of the patientwho possesses a delusion. A delusion, it will be remembered,is a false belief which is impervious to the most complete logicaldemonstration of its impossibility, and unshaken by thepresence of incompatible or obviously contradictory facts.Thus, if a patient believes that he is the king, it is useless toprove conclusively to him that his contention is wrong; heremains serenely unaffected. He is, perhaps, well acquaintedwith the past history of himself and his family, but it neveroccurs to him that the facts contained therein are incompatiblewith the belief that he is the son of George III. He may assureus that he is omnipotent and capable of creating a newuniverse, and yet the next moment he may ask plaintively tobe allowed to leave the hospital, or beg for a small quantityof tobacco. This tissue of contradictions seems at first sightinexplicable and incomprehensible, but the key to the riddleis clear so soon as we realise that the patient's mind is in a stateof dissociation. It no longer presents a homogeneous streamprogressing in a definite direction towards a single end, but iscomposed of more or less isolated mental processes, eachpursuing its own independent development, unaffected by thepresence of its fellows. The patient believes that he is the king,and he is also aware of facts which totally contradict thatbelief; but although both these things exist together in hismind, they are not allowed to come into contact, and each isimpervious to the significance of the other. They pursue theircourses in logic-tight compartments, as it were, separated by

Page 64: The Psychology of Insanity

barriers through which no connecting thought or reasoning ispermitted to pass. Similarly, the patient's belief is unaffectedby our scientific demonstration of its impossibility. He under-stands perfectly each point of our reasoning, but its significanceis not allowed to penetrate the compartment which containshis delusion; it glides off as water glides off a duck's back.

Although the phenomena just described are so bizarre, andso characteristically insane, yet this dissociation of the mindinto logic-tight compartments is by no means confined to thepopulation of the mental hospital. It is a common, and perhapsinevitable, occurrence in the psychology of every humanbeing. Our political convictions are notoriously inaccessible toargument, and we preserve the traditional beliefs of our child-hood in spite of the contradictory facts constantly presentedby our experience. Such phenomena can only be explainedby the existence of a certain amount of dissociation, and,though less in degree, it is precisely similar in kind to thedissociation which permits the asylum queen to scrub the wardfloor, serenely unconscious of the incongruity between herexalted rank and her menial occupation.

51

Page 65: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER V

COMPLEXES

I N chapter in we have described some of the phenomena to beobserved in various morbid states of mind, and in chapter ivwe have endeavoured to arrange these phenomena into groups.This process of classification has enabled us to reduce theoriginal chaos into some sort of order, and to obtain a compre-hensive view of the facts of our subject. We have discovered,for example, that many of the manifestations of mental dis-order are to be regarded as cases of dissociation of conscious-ness—the stream of consciousness is divided into independentcurrents no longer combined into one harmonious whole. Sofar, however, no attempt has been made to explain why thesephenomena occur. We have seen that the imaginary voiceswhich torture the hallucinated patient are nothing but split-offportions of his own consciousness, but we have assigned noreason to account for a portion of consciousness being splitoff in this abnormal manner, nor have we explained why thehallucinatory voice should make remarks of one characterrather than another. We have found, in fact, that certain eventsoccur, but we are still altogether in the dark as to why theyoccur.

The reader who has clearly understood the general principlesenunciated in chapter n will at once perceive that we havecarried out the first two steps of the method of science, buthave as yet made no attempt to proceed to the third step. Thephenomena have been collected and classified; we have still tofind conceptions which will suffice to resume and explain thosephenomena.

This necessary third step is one of great difficulty. Thescience of psychiatry is so young, so much remains to bediscovered, that it is only possible at the present day to advancea short distance in the desired direction. Moreover, even this

52

Page 66: The Psychology of Insanity

short distance will inevitably take us into disputed ground,for the frontier of a youthful science is always the scene ofconstant battle. Hence, although the clear presentation of oursubject will necessitate the adoption of a somewhat dogmaticattitude, the reader must remember that many of the con-clusions reached in this and the following chapters are to beregarded as tentative rather than as firmly established. To alarge extent they are the result of the researches carried out inrecent years by Prof. Freud of Vienna and Dr Jung of Zurich.

Before we endeavour to discover the causes underlyingmorbid psychological phenomena we must be convinced thatour quest is reasonable, we must firmly believe that such causesexist. This belief involves the adoption of psychological deter-minism—the doctrine that in the psychical world, as in theworld of matter, every event must have a cause. Provided thatthe necessary antecedents are present, then the result willinevitably follow; and if we see the result, then we know thatcertain definite causes must have combined in order to produceit. Chance has no more part in psychology than it has inphysics. Every thought which flits through the mind, howevercasual or irrelevant it may seem to be, is the only thoughtwhich can possibly result from the various mental processeswhich preceded it. If I am asked to think of a number, it isapparently a matter of indifference to me which number Iselect. In reality, however, the number is definitely andabsolutely determined by the mental state of the moment—•one particular number will inevitably appear in the mind, noother is possible. This position will perhaps strike the readeras strained and unreal, but unless it is adopted as a preliminaryaxiom, no science of psychology can exist. Whatever our privatephilosophy may be, so long as we are thinking psychologicallyand scientifically, we must subscribe to all the implications ofthe law of causation.

The ascertaining of the causes determining the flow of ourconsciousness is the ultimate aim of psychology. We shallexpect, of course, that the laws discovered will be identicalin the sane and the insane, just as the physiological laws

53 c

Page 67: The Psychology of Insanity

determining the processes of the diseased body are the sameas those determining the processes of the healthy body—thedifference is merely one of degree and combination in thecauses concerned.

Now we may get an idea of the direction in which we shouldsearch for these determinative causes by the consideration ofsome simple examples. Let us suppose that I am an enthu-siastic photographer. It is obvious that the existence of thishobby will continually affect the flow of my consciousness.Scenes which would otherwise be indifferent to me will fre-quently arouse interest as possible material for a picture: if Iperuse a newspaper an article upon photography will at oncearrest my attention, and when I meet my friends I shallprobably seize every opportunity to turn the conversation tomy favourite pursuit. We see, in fact, that the hobby is one ofthe causes determining the direction of my thinking. Now, ifwe endeavour to ascertain the exact nature of a hobby, wefind that it is a system of connected ideas, with a strongemotional tone* and a tendency to produce actions of a certaindefinite character. Such a system of emotionally toned ideasis termed in technical language a * complex5—and a hobby isto be regarded as a particular variety of complex. In the simplecase just described we should say that one of the causes deter-mining the flow of my consciousness was a strong ' photographycomplex'.1

Complexes may be of all sorts and kinds, the componentideas may be of every variety, the accompanying emotionaltones pleasant or painful, very intense or comparatively weak.

When the emotional tone of a complex is very intense, theaction which it exerts upon consciousness becomes correspond-ingly great. Consider, for example, the immensely powerfulcomplex formed in the young man who has recently fallen in

1 The term * complex * was originally devised by Jung, and used by himin the general sense employed in this book. Its connotation has tended tobecome restricted, however, to systems of ideas which are repressed (seechapter vn), and therefore of a more or less morbid character. The moregeneral conception employed in the present chapter corresponds closely tothe 'sentiment' of Shand and McDougall.

54

Page 68: The Psychology of Insanity

love. Ideas belonging to the complex incessantly emerge intoconsciousness, the slightest associative connections sufficingto arouse them. All his mental energy is absorbed in weavingtrains of thought centred in the beloved one, and he cannotdivert his mind to the business of the day. Every event whichhappens is brought into relation with his passion, and thewhole universe is for him nothing but a setting for his domi-nating complex.

Complexes, then, are causes which determine the behaviourof the conscious stream, and the action which they exert uponconsciousness may be regarded as the psychological analogueof the conception of'force' in physics. They are not, of course,constantly active, but only become so under certain conditions.These conditions consist in the presence of a 'stimulus', occur-ring whenever one or more of the ideas belonging to a complexis roused to activity, either by some external event, or byprocesses of association occurring within the mind itself.Thus, in the simple example we have taken the ' photographycomplex' might be stimulated by a conversation in whichsome photographic subject was introduced, or by a chain ofassociations leading from some indifferent idea to an ideadefinitely belonging to the sphere of photography. So soonas this necessary stimulation has occurred, the complex im-mediately tends to exert its effect upon consciousness. Theeffect consists normally in the introduction into consciousnessof ideas, emotions, and trains of activity belonging to thecomplex. Of the Ideas, arguments, etc., presented to the indivi-dual, those which are in harmony with the complex are rein-forced, whereas those not so in harmony tend to be inhibitedand to lose their cogency.

The mode of thought produced in this manner by theactivity of a complex is quite different from that occurring ingenuine logical thinking. In the latter case each step is thelogical consequence of the preceding steps, evidence is im-partially weighed, and the probability of various solutions isdispassionately considered. Such genuine logical thinking is inordinary life comparatively rare; in most cases a 'complex

55

Page 69: The Psychology of Insanity

bias' is only too obvious. Even in the world of science, gener-ally regarded by the ignorant as the peculiar sphere of dis-passionate and cold thought, complexes play a vast part. Thediscussions of any learned society provide most instructivematerial in this respect.

In these systems of emotionally toned ideas we have there-fore found efficient causes which are at any rate partiallyresponsible for the direction of our thoughts and actions. Wemay now proceed a stage further. If we asked the photographerwhy he always thought and acted in certain ways he wouldprobably at once reply, 'Because I am interested in photo-graphy ' ; that is to say, he would himself be aware of the exis-tence of the photography-complex and of the way in which itproduced its effects. This subjective awareness of the existenceand action of a complex is, however, by no means alwayspresent. A complex may exert a pronounced effect upon con-sciousness, although the individual himself may be unawareof its action—that is to say, he may be altogether ignorant ofthe causes which are really determining his own mentalprocesses. An example will help to make this statement intelli-gible. When a party politician is called upon to consider a newmeasure, his verdict is largely determined by certain constantsystems of ideas and trends of thought, constituting what isgenerally known as * party bias'. We should describe thesesystems in our newly acquired terminology as his 'political-complex'. The complex causes him to take up an attitudetowards the proposed measure which is quite independent ofany absolute merits that the latter may possess. If we arguewith our politician, we shall find that the complex will rein-force in his mind those arguments which support the view ofhis party, while it will.infallibly prevent him from realising theforce of the arguments propounded by the opposite side. Nowit should be observed that the individual himself is probablyquite unaware of this mechanism in his mind. He fondlyimagines that his opinion is formed solely by the logical prosand cons of the measure before him. We see, in fact, that notonly is his thinking determined by a complex of whose action

56

Page 70: The Psychology of Insanity

he is unconscious, but he believes his thoughts to be the resultof other causes which are in reality insufficient and illusory.This latter process of self-deception, in which the individualconceals the real foundation of his thought by a series ofadventitious props, is termed * rationalisation'.

The two mechanisms which manifest themselves in ourexample of the politician, the unconscious origin of beliefs andactions, and the subsequent process of rationalisation to whichthey are subjected, are of fundamental importance in psycho-logy. They may be observed every day in every individual.That a man generally knows why he thinks in a certain way,and why he does certain things, is a widespread and cherishedbelief of the human race. It is, unfortunately, for the mostpart an erroneous one. We have an overwhelming need tobelieve that we are acting rationally, and are loath to admit thatwe think and do things without being ourselves aware of themotives producing those thoughts and actions. Now a verylarge number of our mental processes are the result of an emo-tional bias or complex of the type we have described. Such acausal chain is, however, incompatible with our ideal of ration-ality. Hence we tend to substitute for it a fictitious logicalprocess, and persuade ourselves that the particular thought oraction is its reasonable and natural result. This is the mechan-ism of rationalisation seen in the example of the politician; weshall meet with further illustrations of its effects throughoutthe whole sphere of normal and abnormal, psychology.

The prevalence of 'rationalisation* is responsible for theerroneous belief that reason, taken in the sense of logicaldeduction from given premisses, plays the dominating rolein the formation of human thought and conduct. In most casesthe thought or action makes its appearance without any suchantecedent process, moulded by the various complexesresulting from our instincts and experience. The 'reason* isevolved subsequently, to satisfy our craving for rationality.

The mechanism of rationalisation is most evident, perhaps,in the sphere of moral conduct, where we tend always toascribe our actions to a conscious application of certain general

57

Page 71: The Psychology of Insanity

religious or ethical principles. The majority of such actionsare the result of habit, obedience to the traditions of our class,and other similar causes, and are carried out instinctively andimmediately. The general principle is only produced subse-quently, when we are challenged to explain our conduct. Whenthe principle and the action do not entirely accord with eachother, we amend the former by further rationalisations untilit is capable of posing as the explanation of the latter, and inthis way preserve our ideal of rationality. Thus it is a familiarfact that people of otherwise irreproachable honesty willswindle the government or a railway company with untroubledequanimity. If they are taxed with the incongruity betweentheir principles and their conduct, a varied crop of rational-isations will be immediately produced. They will point outthat a company is not the same thing as an individual, thatnobody really loses anything, that the fares or taxes are soinequitable that it is justifiable to evade them, and so on.The distinction between the real and apparent causes of mentalprocesses is well illustrated in the advice given to the newlycreated judge, * Give your decision, it will probably be right.But do not give your reasons, they will almost certainly bewrong.'

It will be obvious, therefore, that to ask a man why he doesa certain thing is by no means an invariably efficient methodof discovering the genuine causes underlying his action.Introspection, however honestly it may be carried out, fre-quently fails when it attempts more than the mere recordingof the superficial contents of consciousness. So soon as it aimsat the elucidation of the real springs of action, there is alwaysthe possibility that either no result whatever is obtainable, orone vitiated by the mechanism of rationalisation. This fact isof primary importance, even to the psychologist who concernshimself only with the normal mind. For the investigator whoextends his researches to the sphere of the abnormal, itpossesses a significance which cannot be overestimated. Thatsignificance will be better appreciated, however, when we haveproceeded further in our discussion of the action of complexes.

58

Page 72: The Psychology of Insanity

Various elaborate methods have been devised by which thisdifficulty in investigation may be overcome, and by which thecomplexes really responsible for the mental processes presentmay be laid bare. For the most part they require considerableknowledge and experience before they can be satisfactorilyemployed, and any adequate description of the procedurenecessary is altogether impossible within the limits of this book.We may be permitted, however, to digress for a moment intothe field of experimental psychology, and to devote a fewwords to the interesting method introduced by Jung, which isof great service in psychological investigations.

A list of words is read out to the patient, and in response toeach he is required to give the first word which occurs to him.The word read out is known as the stimulus word, and thepatient's reply is termed the reaction word. Generally it isfound that the latter is related to the former by some simpleassociative link. Thus, to the stimulus word ' table' the reactionword ' chair' might be given, or some other simple associationof a similar character. The time elapsing between the callingout of the stimulus word and the patient's reply is known asthe reaction time, and is carefully measured by means of astop-watch.

Now Jung found that the reaction obtained varied consider-ably, according as the stimulus word had or had not arouseda complex to activity. The reactions characteristic of the ac-tivity of a complex exhibited increase of the reaction time andvarious peculiarities in the reaction word. The followingexample, given by Jung and Peterson, illustrates some of thepoints in question:

(sec.)Stimulus wordi2

34567

HeadGreenWaterStickLongShipAsk

Reaction wordHairMeadowDeepKnifeTableSinkAnswer

Reaction timei * 4

5'°i - 6I -2

3*4i -6

59

Page 73: The Psychology of Insanity

Stimulus word89

IOI I

12I *

WoolSpitefulLakeSickInkSwim

Reaction wordKnitFriendlyWaterWellBlackCan swim

Reaction time (sec.)

i - 44-o

I *23-8

The patient from whom this series was obtained had, duringa recent attack of depression, determined to commit suicide bydrowning. This complex had manifested itself in the associa-tions which are italicised. 3, 6, 10, and 13 are instances ofincreased reaction time; 13 shows also a peculiarity in thereaction word itself.

As a result of his researches, Jung maintained that by meansof the association experiment it was possible to obtain in-formation concerning the principal complexes in the mindof a given subject. This method has now been considerablydeveloped and elaborated. It is of great service in the pre-liminary investigation of a case, and often furnishes valuableindications of the directions along which a subsequent detailedanalysis may most profitably be conducted.1

We must now resume the thread of our original inquiry,and continue our discussion of the mode in which the actionof complexes is manifested in the production of thoughts andactions.

In the examples of the photographer and the politician thecomplex expresses itself directly, that is to say, the photo-graphy-complex causes the man to think 'photographically5,the political-complex causes him to think politically. But oftenthe complex expresses itself indirectly by some manifestationwhich at first sight seems altogether different in nature. Wemay illustrate the meaning of this statement by the followingexample: one of my patients, a former Sunday-school teacher,

1 The subsequent history of the association test has not fulfilled the ex-pectation that it would be of great value in the psychological analysis ofpatients. It still provides an interesting sphere of experimental investigation,but is only occasionally used in practical medical treatment.

60

Page 74: The Psychology of Insanity

had become a convinced atheist. He insisted that he hadreached this standpoint after a long and careful study of theliterature of the subject, and, as a matter of fact, he really hadacquired a remarkably wide knowledge of religious apolo-getics. He discoursed at length upon the evidence of Genesis,marshalling his arguments with considerable skill, and pro-ducing a coherent and well-reasoned case. Subsequent psycho-logical analysis, however, revealed the real complex responsiblefor his atheism; the girl to whom he had been engaged hadeloped with the most enthusiastic of his fellow Sunday-schoolteachers. We see that in this patient the causal complex, resent-ment against his successful rival, had expressed itself by arepudiation of the beliefs which had formerly constituted theprincipal bond between them. The arguments, the study,and the quotations were merely an elaborate rationalisation.

Here is another example of indirect expression of a complex,occurring in the same case. The patient had been for some timeon bad terms with his father, to whom he was, nevertheless,very sincerely attached. The father's persistent refusal toentertain any proposals of reconciliation was a source of greatdistress to my patient. On one occasion the latter came to mein an unusually depressed frame of mind. He stated that on themorning in question he had seen two foreigners badly treated,and the occurrence has so revolted him that he had felt com-pletely upset for the remainder of the day. I was sufficientlyacquainted with the psychology of his case to realise that thealleged cause was quite insufficient to account for the mentalstate present, and I therefore proceeded to a more thoroughinvestigation. Analysis soon revealed the real causal complex.The patient had that morning received a letter from hisfather containing the usual abuses and reproaches. The actualcause of the depression was the ill-treatment which he hadhimself experienced from his father, the troubles of the twoforeigners merely serving the purpose of a rationalisation.

As a simpler and more familiar example of indirect expres-sion of a complex we may cite a case mentioned by Jung.A man walking with a friend in the neighbourhood of a

61

Page 75: The Psychology of Insanity

country village, suddenly expressed extreme irritation con-cerning the church bells, which happened to be pealing at themoment. He maintained that their tone was intrinsicallyunpleasant, their harmony ugly, and the total effect altogetherdisagreeable. The friend was astonished, for the bells in ques-tion were famous for their singular beauty. He endeavoured,therefore, to elucidate the real cause underlying his com-panion's attitude. Skilful questioning elicited the furtherremark that not only were the bells unpleasant but the clergy-man of the church wrote extremely bad poetry. The causalcomplex was then apparent, for the man whose ears had beenoffended by the bells also wrote poetry, and in a recent criti-cism his work had been compared very unfavourably with thatof the clergyman. The rivalry-complex thus engendered hadexpressed itself indirectly by an unjustifiable denunciation ofthe innocent church bells. The direct expression would, ofcourse, have been abuse of the clergyman himself or of hisworks.

It will be observed that, without the subsequent analysis,the behaviour of the man would have appeared inexplicable,or at best ascribable to 'bad temper5, 'irritability5, or someother not very satisfying reason. Most cases where suddenpassion over some trifle is witnessed may be explained alongsimilar lines, and demonstrated to be the effect of some otherand quite adequate cause. The apparently incomprehensiblereaction is then seen to be the natural resultant of perfectlydefinite antecedents.

It will be profitable here to interrupt our investigations fora moment, in order to consider the position now reached, andthe possible inferences which may be drawn to aid us in ourattack upon the problems of mental disorder. We have foundthat the processes of the normal mind are in part the result ofcauses or 'complexes5, of whose action the individual himselfmay be altogether unconscious. Secondly, the action of suchcomplexes may be indirect, so that the conscious processesproduced may have but little prima facie relation to the causesresponsible for them. Thirdly, the individual may believe his

62

Page 76: The Psychology of Insanity

thoughts or actions to be the results of other causes, which havein reality played no part whatever in their production, but areonly the effects of a subsequent process of rationalisation.

These various mechanisms will obscure, both for himself andfor the observer, the efficient causes responsible for the indivi-dual's train of thought or action. The efficient causes will notbe those lying upon the surface, but deeper processes only tobe unravelled by a delicate psychological analysis. Now it ispossible that mechanisms of a similar nature may play a partin the production of the symptoms of insanity, and that thesesymptoms may be the indirect and distorted expressions ofhidden complexes. In that case their apparent incompre-hensibility would be due merely to our ignorance of thesecomplexes and would vanish so soon as the latter wereunearthed. The exaggerated misery of the melancholic patientover some inadequate and absurd idea would lose its appear-ance of inadequacy and absurdity if we could demonstratethat it was really the result of some other and quite efficientcause, just as the incomprehensible irritation, apparentlyproduced in Jung's patient by the church bells, was fullyexplained when the underlying mental processes were laidbare. Similarly the delusions exhibited by some of our patientsmight not seem such grotesque and baseless anomalies if weceased to take them at their face value, and insisted on delvingdeeper into the mind. Possibly we should then discover themto be merely indirect expressions, or perhaps attempts atrationalisation, of underlying processes which in themselvesmight be perfectly reasonable and coherent.

The hypothesis that the insane mind is not the chaos whicha superficial observer imagines it to be, but that the appear-ance of disorder is due only to our ignorance of the deepermental processes which link up the disjointed symptoms intoa coherent whole, is at any rate suggestive and stimulating.Subsequent chapters will show, as a matter of fact, that recentpsychological researches justify and confirm it to a very largeextent. We shall hope to demonstrate that the thoughts andactions of the insane are not a meaningless and inscrutable

63

Page 77: The Psychology of Insanity

medley, but that cause and effect play as considerable a part inthe mind of the apparently incomprehensible insane patientas in that of the normal man. We shall find reason to believe,moreover, that not only are the mental processes of the insaneexplicable by psychological laws, but these laws are identicalwith those governing the minds of the sane, that the insanepatient is battling with the same troubles which beset us all,and that he is endeavouring to express ideas, desires, andambitions, with which we are all acquainted.

Page 78: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER VI

CONFLICT

W E have described in the last chapter certain psychologicallaws which are constantly to be found in action both in thenormal and in the insane mind. An attentive examination ofthe phenomena in which those laws are manifested, will con-vince us, however, that the position so far reached can in nosense be regarded as final. Further problems at once suggestthemselves. Why is an individual sometimes aware of the com-plexes determining his thoughts and actions, and sometimesnot so aware? Why does a complex in one instance expressitself simply and immediately, in another by those deviousroutes which we have termed s indirect' ? Why does the father'sletter make my patient miserable about the two foreigners,instead of making him miserable about the father's treatmentof himself? The answers to these questions involve two furtherpsychological conceptions, those of'conflict' and 'repression'.These conceptions are of fundamental importance, and it willbe necessary to examine them at considerable length.

Suppose that a complex is for some reason out of harmonywith the mind as a whole, perhaps because of its intrinsicallypainful nature, perhaps because it prompts to actions whichare incompatible with the individual's general views andprinciples. In such a case a state of'conflict' arises, a struggle,as it were, between the complex and the personality.1 Thesetwo forces will tend mutually to inhibit each other, the mindwill be divided against itself, and a paralysis of action will

1 'Personality' is used here to denote all the mental processes—ideas,emotions, memories, desires—which do not belong to the complex inquestion. That is to say, it denotes the whole of the mind with the exceptionof the particular complex which is under discussion at the moment. Thisdivision of the mind into two parts is only a more exact description of thatcurrently implied when, for example, we speak of a man conquering, oracceding to, a desire or temptation.

65

Page 79: The Psychology of Insanity

ensue. The conception of conflict may be illustrated by anadaptation of our former example of the lover. Let usassume that the object of his passion is already the wife ofanother man. The lover's mind will then exhibit two com-plexes trending in opposite and incompatible directions, onthe one hand the desire for the woman, on the other theopposing tendencies constituted by moral education and fearof consequences. Under such circumstances neither is able toexpress itself freely in appropriate action, and a state of conflictresults. This state of conflict is characterised by a condition ofunpleasant emotional tension: the individual feels himself tornbetween two lines of conduct, neither of which is possible onaccount of the resistance offered by the other.

Conflict, with its emotional tension and accompanyingindecision and paralysis of action, cannot persist indefinitely;it is a biological necessity that some solution of the difficulty,some way out of the impasse, should be found. This necessarysolution may be attained in many different ways. For example,the complex may be modified so that its incompatibility withthe personality no longer exists, or the mind may clearlyrecognise that the two possible ends cannot both be achievedand, after due weighing of the merits of each, consciouslydecide that one must be abandoned in favour of the other.

This subjective appreciation of the forces at war within us,and deliberate adoption of a consciously selected line of con-duct, may be regarded as the rational or ideal solution of aconflict. In fact it may be said to provide the only possiblesolution in the strict sense of the word. In those other methodswhich we are now about to describe, the mind rids itself of theemotional tension and paralysis of action, not by a fight to afinish, but by a process of avoiding the conflict altogether. Themind is saved from the stress and strain of battle, because thetwo antagonists are not allowred to meet.

The first of these methods consists in the simple expedientof preserving both the opposing groups of ideas in the mind,while at the same time all contact or interaction between themis sedulously avoided. Each is allowed to pursue its own course

66

Page 80: The Psychology of Insanity

and development, untroubled by its incongruity with theother. A mind exhibiting this phenomenon may be comparedto an orchestra where one instrumentalist plays some indepen-dent melody of his own choosing, unconcerned by the discordhe creates with the concerted harmony of his fellows. This isthe common mechanism of the 'logic-tight compartment',which we have already met with in the chapter upon 'dissocia-tion5. By its aid the jman whose morality in private life isunimpeachable is enabled to practise a quite different moralcode so far as his commercial transactions are concerned,because the two spheres of action are kept rigidly apart in hismind. It provides the explanation of the well-known antithesisbetween precept and practice, and enables us to understandthat large section of the human race, often erroneouslyregarded as conscious hypocrites,

Whose life laughs through and spits at their creed,Who maintain Thee in word, and defy Thee in deed.

The same mechanism explains the inability of the lover toappreciate the obvious imperfections of his lady: he cannot seethem because his mind will not see them, the disturbing factsare not allowed to come into contact with his passions and theopinions which result therefrom. In a similar way we preservethe traditional beliefs of our childhood, whatever contradic-tory facts our experience may subsequently have presentedto us. No conflict arises, because the beliefs and the facts live inseparate logic-tight compartments of our minds, and are neverpermitted to come face to face in the field of consciousness.

It were easy to multiply indefinitely illustrations fromnormal life of this method of treating incompatible mentalfactors by the simple process of mutual exclusion. Honestintrospection will no doubt furnish the reader with copiousexamples from his own mental life, or, if he finds this taskinsuperable, he will have no difficulty in observing the mech-anism at work in the minds of his neighbours.

Here, however, we must pass on into the sphere of theabnormal, and endeavour to discover whether, and to what

67

Page 81: The Psychology of Insanity

extent, this principle is evident in the phenomena of insanity.We find, as a matter of fact, that it plays a very large part inthose phenomena, and that it renders intelligible a whole groupof facts generally regarded as peculiarly characteristic of theinsane. The patient who believes herself to be a queen, butwho nevertheless cheerfully and contentedly carries out herdaily task of scrubbing the ward, is not perturbed by theincongruity between her beliefs and conduct. The conflictbetween the two is avoided by the process of not allowing themto confront one another in the field of consciousness; the delu-sion is preserved in a logic-tight compartment secure from thedisturbing influence of hard facts. By this means the com-plexes underlying the delusion, complexes whose nature weshall study at a subsequent stage of our investigations, succeedin obtaining expression in spite of the incompatible processespresent in the remainder of the mind. Similarly those othercases mentioned at the conclusion of chapter iv—the patientwho believes that he is the son of George III although he is atthe same time perfectly aware of the actual past history ofhimself and his family, the patient who claims that he isomnipotent but who implores the gift of a little tobacco—theseare all examples of the mechanism of the logic-tight com-partment. In all of them contradictory systems of ideas arepresent in the mind, but conflict is avoided by allowing eachsystem to develop independently, secure from contact with anyidea or fact which may be incompatible therewith.

It will be remembered that in chapter iv these instanceswere cited as examples of dissociation. We have, therefore,now carried our investigation a stage further, and havediscovered the mechanism upon which this dissociationdepends. The mind has lost its homogeneity and is composed ofmore or less isolated mental processes, each pursuing its ownindependent course unaffected by the presence of its fellows,simply because those mental processes were contradictory andincompatible, and the conflict between them has beenavoided by dissociating one from the others. The splitting ofthe mind has taken place because the two opponents could not

68

Page 82: The Psychology of Insanity

be reconciled, and the device of permitting each to occupy itsown logic-tight compartment afforded the easiest method ofavoiding the otherwise inevitable conflict. From the standpointnow reached we may therefore lay down the principle that, insome cases at least, dissociation is the result of conflict, andthat it is one of the methods by which the mind gets rid of theunpleasant emotional tension and paralysis of action thatconflict invariably produces. The hypothesis immediatelysuggests itself, moreover, that all cases of dissociation, all thosevarying grades described in chapter iv, somnambulism, doublepersonalities, obsessions, hallucinations, and delusions, maypossibly be due to a similar mechanism. Dissociation wouldthen always indicate the presence of a mental conflict, andwould acquire the significance of a defensive reaction adoptedby the mind when confronted with two incompatible systemsof ideas. We shall subsequently find that a large number ofvarying grades of dissociation are, as a matter of fact, capableof being explained by this hypothesis, and that the evidencein its favour is very convincing. For the moment, however,it is necessary to retrace our steps and to modify in some degreecertain of the principles already laid down.

It has been stated that a common method of avoidingconflict, in both the normal and the insane mind, consists in theprocess of dissociating the two opposing systems of ideas so thateach is permitted to pursue its own development uninfluencedby its incongruity with the other. In the description of theexamples used to illustrate this method it was further statedthat a complex was thus segregated in a logic-tight compart-ment, into which no contradicting fact or idea was allowed toenter. That is to say, the complex preserves its freedom fromconflict by simply neglecting altogether the significance of anyfact or idea which is incompatible with it: contact betweenthe two is completely avoided. Now although this statement isliterally true of a small number of cases, the actual state ofaffairs is in most instances somewhat more complicated. Con-tact between the two opposing systems of ideas can rarelybe avoided in the completely efficient manner which our

69

Page 83: The Psychology of Insanity

description suggests. The opposing systems do come into contact,but only through a medium which so distorts the connectingprocesses that the real significance of the incompatible forcesis concealed, and the mind fails to appreciate that any actualcontradiction is present. This distorting medium is providedby the mechanism of rationalisation. Rationalisation, in-stances of which we have already met with in chapter iv,allows the mind to regard the facts incompatible with thecomplex in such a light that their incompatibility is more orless efficiently cloaked. This conception of two opposinggroups of ideas, only allowed to come into contact through thedistorting medium of rationalisation, will be made clearer bythe consideration of some specific examples. The man whosecommercial morality differs fundamentally from the codewhich he practises in his private life, persuades himself thatthe latter code is not properly applicable to business relations,that to ask a customer three times the value of a certain articleis obviously something quite different from thieving, that aman must live, and that the immorality of lying completelydisappears when it is necessary for the support of one's wife andfamily. Whenever, in fact, our actions conflict with our ethicalprinciples we seek for specious reasons which will enable us toregard the actions in question as a peculiar case altogetherjustified by the circumstances in which they are carried out.The example cited in chapter v, of the honest man who swin-dles the railway company and the government without in anyway injuring his sense of personal rectitude, provides an excel-lent illustration of the process we are now describing. In allthese cases the incompatible systems of ideas are allowed tocome into contact, but only by means of a bridge of ration-alisations which so distorts their mutual significance thatconflict is efficiently avoided. That is to say, the separatecompartment of the mind in which the complex pursues itsdevelopment is 'logic-tight5, but not 'idea-tight'; opposingideas are allowed to enter, but only after their logical signifi-cance has been distorted by a process of rationalisation.

If we now turn again to the sphere of the abnormal we shall

70

Page 84: The Psychology of Insanity

find that the mechanism of rationalisation plays a very pro-minent part. The patient who possesses a delusion neglects asfar as possible the facts which are incompatible with his belief,but if he is compelled to take them into account he rationalisesthem in such a way that their actual significance is effectuallyconcealed. Thus, the patient who is firmly convinced that hiswife is seeking to murder him, will distort the meaning ofeverything which happens until it is brought into harmonywith his dominating delusion, and capable of being used as apseudo-logical prop. If his wife is solicitous for his welfare herbehaviour is regarded as a cloak to conceal her real design,if she treats him badly the evil intentions are clear, if she giveshim food it is obvious that she proposes to poison him, if shedoes not it is equally obvious that she hopes to undermine hishealth by withholding the necessaries of life. If we argue withhim and point out that his belief is inconsistent with the facts,he smiles contemptuously at our credulity, or is perhaps sus-picious that we are the paid accomplices of his wife.

This mechanism is responsible for a large group of thephenomena of insanity which may be termed 'secondarydelusions*. 'Secondary delusions' are erroneous beliefserected by the mind in order to bridge over the incongruitybetween the primary delusion and the actual facts of thepatient's experience. For example, the patient who believesthat he is a millionaire will meet the obvious fact that he hasnot a penny in his pocket by developing the further belief thathe is the victim of an organised plot to deprive him of hisproperty. Delusions of grandeur are, indeed, almost invariablyaccompanied by delusions of persecution. The patient cannotconceal from himself that his claims to exalted rank andposition are not recognised by his environment, but herationalises this failure of recognition by persuading himselfthat it is the work of a malignant and envious enemy. In thisway the most complicated delusional systems may arise, thepatient being convinced that more and more elaborate perse-cutions are being employed the more he meets with evidencecontradicting the primary belief.

Page 85: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER VII

REPRESSION

I N the last chapter we have dealt with the general question ofmental conflict, and have discussed one of the methods bywhich the mind may avoid the internal stress and accompany-ing disagreeable emotional tension which a state of conflictinevitably produces. This method, characterised by the forma-tion in the mind of * logic-tight compartments', accounts, aswe have seen, not only for many of the phenomena observedin everyday life but also for some of the secondary phenomenamet with in insanity.

Sometimes, however, this simple method of avoidance isnot available, and the mind may then resort to other ways offreeing itself from the stresses and strains of conflict. Themajority of these other methods are included under thegeneral conception of'repression', and we must now proceedto examine this conception and the various phenomena whichit serves to explain.

The precise conditions under which the mechanism of the'logic-tight compartment' can no longer be employed are atpresent imperfectly understood. The factors which play theprincipal part therein can, however, probably be summarisedin the two following groups. First, the complexes at war withone another may be of such intrinsic importance and strengththat the conflict between them cannot be concealed from themind by the simple process of allowing each to pursue its ownindependent course and development. Secondly, the mind maybe of a relatively more sensitive type which detects at once theunsatisfactory nature of this procedure. That is to say, themind may be constitutionally endowed with a capacity forclear self-criticism, such that it is unable to delude itself by theeasy mechanism of the logic-tight compartment, and cannotbe satisfied by the very obvious rationalisations which that

72

Page 86: The Psychology of Insanity

mechanism employs. Under these circumstances either themind must face the conflict and fight it to a finish in the waywe have previously described, or it must resort to the moreelaborate methods of avoidance which are included under theconception of'repression'.

In the method of the logic-tight compartment each of theopposing complexes is allowed a place in the field of con-sciousness. In the mechanism of repression, however, conflictis avoided by banishing one of the opponents from conscious-ness and no longer allowing it to achieve its normal expression,while the other opponent is left in possession of the field. Thisprocess of banishing a complex, so that it is prevented fromappearing in consciousness, is the essential character of themechanism of repression. Its nature will be best understoodby the consideration of a simple example. Let us suppose thata man has in the past done some action of which he is nowashamed, so that every time the thought of this action recursto him it occasions painful feelings of remorse. Expressing thisstate of affairs in our technical language, we should say that thememory of the action forms a complex which is repugnant tothe personality as a whole, and that therefore a conflict is setup between the complex and the personality. Under suchcircumstances the individual may endeavour to rid himself ofthe feelings of remorse by striving to banish the painfulmemories from his mind, to keep them studiously out of histhoughts, and so far as possible to ignore their existence. Thatis to say, he may endeavour to avoid the conflict by ' repressing'the offending complex, and shutting it out from the field ofconsciousness. This method of attaining peace of mind byrefusing to acknowledge to ourselves the existence of unplea-sant facts which would otherwise grievously disquiet us willbe familiar to everybody. Much of the 'forgetting' whichoccurs in our lives is not the passive process of decay which itis commonly supposed to be, but an active repression, adeliberate exclusion of the offending memory from the sphereof our consciousness.

In so far as the repression is successful the complex is

73

Page 87: The Psychology of Insanity

dislocated from the remainder of the mind, and thrown out ofgear, as it were, with the personality. It is banished from thefield of consciousness, and can no longer manifest itself there inthe normal manner described in chapter v; that is to say, thecomplex can no longer cause the direct introduction intoconsciousness of the ideas, emotions, and trains of activitybelonging to it.

Although the complex is thus forbidden to manifest itself inthe field of consciousness, we assume, for reasons which willpresently be clear, that it does not thereby cease to exist. Thecomplex is not annihilated, but is shut out, and deprived of itsnormal functions. It persists in the deeper layers of the mind,as it were, although it is prevented from rising to the surfaceby the constant resistance which the repressive process opposesto it.

It will be evident that repression is/a more drastic methodof dealing with conflict than that offered by the * logic-tightcompartment', and that its disturbing effect upon the homo-geneity and unity of the mind will be proportionally greater.Hence, although repression in its minor degrees is by no meansuncommon in everyday life, for its more pronounced mani-festations we must turn to the sphere of the definitely abnor-mal. We shall, indeed, best achieve a clear understanding ofits action by proceeding at once to those examples whererepression produces its most marked effects. Such examplesare provided by the cases described in chapter in, under theheadings of somnambulism and double personality.

Let us consider, in the light of the conceptions now at ourdisposal, the case of the patient Irene (p. 33). It will beremembered that Irene's mental troubles dated from theillness and death of her mother. The circumstances connectedwith the death were peculiarly painful, and the event pro-duced a profound shock upon Irene's mind. She had beendeeply attached to her mother, and the latter had filled thechief place in all her thoughts, ambitions, and activities. Hermother's death, therefore, not only produced a great griefbut deprived all those ambitions and activities of their main

74

Page 88: The Psychology of Insanity

object and end. We may translate this state of affairs into ourtechnical language as follows: the ideas connected with themother's illness and death formed a system or complex in-tensely painful and repugnant to the personality as a whole.A conflict, with all its accompanying emotional stress andtension, was thus produced between the personality and thecomplex in question. To get rid of this conflict the mechanismof repression was brought into play. The painful complex wasdislocated from the remainder of the mind, and no longerallowed to introduce its constituent ideas and emotions intothe field of consciousness. Hence we find that Irene, inthe intervals between her somnambulisms, had forgotten thewhole system of ideas connected with her mother's death, andremembered nothing of the illness or its tragic end. Shediscussed her mother calmly, and as if nothing had happenedto disturb the tenor of her own life. It will be seen, therefore,that the mechanism of repression had fulfilled its purpose:the conflict and its painful emotions were avoided, becauseone of the opposing complexes was altogether eliminatedfrom the field of consciousness.

Now, it has been stated above that a complex which is thusrepressed is not annihilated, but continues to exist in the deeperlayers of the mind. The reasons which justify this hypothesisare clearly apparent in the case that we are now discussing.The complex which Irene has so efficiently repressed demon-strates its continued existence by suddenly erupting, as it were,and occupying for a time the whole field of consciousness.This is the state of affairs present during the periods of som-nambulism. The system of ideas associated with the mother'sillness suddenly makes its appearance and Irene lives oncemore through the whole tragic scene.

It must be carefully observed that, even during the som-nambulisms, the mechanism of repression is still efficient.The complex which was formerly repressed is now in possessionof the stage, but it possesses the whole stage, and all other ideasare temporarily abolished. While the somnambulism is inprogress Irene is wholly absorbed in her phantasy, and

75

Page 89: The Psychology of Insanity

altogether oblivious of her actual environment, and of what istaking place around her. That is to say, the complete dissocia-tion between the opposing complexes which constitutes theessential feature of repression is still present, and the resistancewhich keeps them apart is as potent as ever. The complexwhich was formerly submerged is now able to express itselffreely, but only because its opponent, represented here by theremainder of the personality, has in turn been shut out fromthe field of consciousness.

The conception of repression, therefore, enables us to explainyet another group of the dissociations of consciousness de-scribed in chapter iv. In the case of somnambulisms the com-plex underlying the dissociated system is in a state of repression,and deprived of its normal interplay with the remainder of themind. It is, therefore, only able to express itself in the field ofconsciousness by the production of ideas and images which aresharply cut off from the remainder of the conscious stream.In other words, the ideas due to the activity of the complexform a completely segregated or dissociated group.

It has been pointed out, in chapter iv, that the conditionknown as 'double personality' differs from somnambulismonly in degree. In both cases we are dealing with systems ofideas which are completely dissociated from the remainderof the mind, but in double personality the dissociated sys-tem is more complicated and complete in its structure, sothat while it occupies the stage, the individual is still able toadapt himself to his environment, and does not exhibit thatabsolute oblivion of the real world which characterises thesomnambulist.

In view of this similarity, we may assume that the explan-ation given for somnambulisms is probably also applicable todouble personalities, and that these dissociations are likewisedue to a conflict between incompatible complexes which hasbeen solved by a process of repression. As a matter of fact, suchan explanation has been successfully applied to a considerablenumber of cases. Limitations of space, however, do not permitof any satisfactory description of them here.

76

Page 90: The Psychology of Insanity

It has been stated above that the group of dissociations,comprising somnambulisms and other closely allied pheno-mena, shows us the mechanism of repression in its clearest andmost pronounced form. Repression, however, manifests itselfin many other ways which, though less obvious and drasticthan the methods just described, will be more familiar to thestudent of everyday life. These other manifestations form thesubject-matter of the following chapter.

77

Page 91: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER VIII

MANIFESTATIONS OF REPRESSED

COMPLEXES

I N the last chapter it has been explained that when a complexis repressed it is thereby deprived of its normal mode ofexpression. That is to say, it can no longer cause its constituentideas and emotions to enter directly into consciousness, and itcan no longer cause the conscious stream to move along acourse which will satisfy its own ends. These effects are pro-duced because a certain resistance, or 'censure* as it is tech-nically termed, is opposed to the normal action of the complex.Our understanding of this conception will perhaps be assisted

Fig. i

by the consideration of the above diagrams which must, ofcourse, be regarded as purely schematic.

Fig. i represents the normal action of a complex. S is thestream of consciousness, the succession of thoughts, emotions,and volitions which occupy the surface, as it were, of ourminds. S corresponds, in fact, to the mind as it appears toordinary introspection. C is a complex, and d represents thevarious ideas, etc., which the complex throws into the streamof consciousness so soon as it is stimulated in the mannerdescribed in chapter v.

Fig. 2 represents the state of affairs which arises if the com-plex is subjected to repression. A resistance (R) is now opposedto the normal action of the complex, so that the ideas belong-ing to the latter can no longer be thrown directly into the

78

Page 92: The Psychology of Insanity

conscious stream in the manner shown in Fig. i. Fig. 2 will,for example, illustrate the conditions present in Irene's mindduring the interval between her somnambulisms. In this caseC would represent the complex connected with the mother'sillness and death. Owing to the presence of the resistance (R),all the ideas belonging to that complex would be absolutelycut off from the stream of consciousness, and we should havethat localised loss of memory which Irene actually exhibitedduring the periods in question.

It was further stated in the preceding chapter that, althoughthe repressed complex is thus deprived of its normal mode ofexpression, it does not thereby cease to exist. We must nowadd that it not only continues to exist, but continues to findexpression, although that expression is no longer normal anddirect. In the case of Irene the complex achieved expressionby so interrupting the stream of consciousness that the portionof the stream in which it appeared, i.e. the somnambulism,was absolutely cut off from that which preceded it and fromthat which followed it. More generally, however, the mode ofexpression is less drastic than this, and is of the type shown inFig. 3. The repressed complex cannot affect consciousness inthe normal direct manner, but it nevertheless contrives toexert an influence along the devious and indirect path repre-sented by 8. This path must be sufficiently devious and indirectto enable the complex to elude, as it were, the resistance (R),and the stronger the resistance the more indirect must the pathof expression become.

The actual facts corresponding to the scheme shown in Fig. 3will be rendered clear by the consideration of a specificinstance, and for this purpose we may select the exampleborrowed from Dr Jung which was described upon p. 61.A certain man expressed extreme annoyance at some irre-proachable church bells. Investigation revealed the fact thatthe man and the clergyman who was attached to the churchwere rivals in the field of amateur poetry. Now the causalcomplex responsible for the phenomena evidently originatedin jealousy of a successful rival. But jealousy of this kind is an

79

Page 93: The Psychology of Insanity

emotion whose existence we are rarely ready to acknowledge,even to ourselves. In other words, it forms a complex which isalmost invariably repressed so far as we are able. A resistanceis imposed which prevents the complex making its appearancein the field of consciousness. Hence the complex is compelledto express itself by some indirect path which will enable it toelude the resistance. In the present case this indirect path wasprovided by an unjustified criticism of the bells which wereclosely connected with the offending clergyman. By this meansthe complex found expression, while the individual was able topersuade himself that his action was due to a quite differentcause. The resistance served its purpose by protecting con-sciousness from the direct manifestation of the unacknowledgedcomplex, so that the conflict which would otherwise havearisen was avoided.

A similar explanation may be applied to the case, describedon p. 61, of the patient who was so distressed at the ill-treat-ment meted out to two foreigners. The causal complex was theresentment which the patient felt at the ill-treatment that hehad himself received from his father. But this complex wasrepressed because it was incompatible with the deep affectionwhich he entertained for his father, and because a distressingconflict would otherwise have inevitably been engendered.Hence it obtained expression in the indirect manner described,by attaching its constituent emotion to an external eventconnected with the real cause by a relation of superficialsimilarity. The other examples of indirect expression of acomplex cited in chapter iv are explicable along similar lines.

At the beginning of chapter vi the problem presented itselfas to why a complex should in one case express itself simply anddirectly, in another by the devious routes termed 'indirect'.This problem we are now in a position to answer. A complexwill express itself directly when it is not subjected to repression.A repressed complex, on the other hand, can influence thestream of consciousness only along an indirect path, becauseof the resistance which is offered by the 'censure'. Owing tothis resistance the manifestations must be so distorted that its

80

Page 94: The Psychology of Insanity

real origin in the tabooed complex is no longer apparent to theindividual. Hence, whenever indirect expression of a complexis observed, it may be assumed that incompatible and conflict-ing systems of ideas are present in the mind, and that thecomplex in question is subjected to some degree of repression.

Now the solution of a mental conflict by the mechanismof repression is one of the commonest refuges of the humanmind. We shall find that it not only explains the occurrence ofphenomena frequently seen in everyday life, but also enables usto understand the genesis of many abnormal mental symptomswhich are observed in the sphere of insanity. It will thereforebe necessary to consider this mechanism in considerable detail.

A study of the diagrams on p. 78 will suggest to us that thephenomena caused by the presence of a repressed complexwill be of two kinds. Either they will be indirect expressionsof the complex itself, or they will be phenomena due to theresistance or ' censure' which forbids the complex to obtain itsnormal and direct expression. As a matter of fact we shall findthat most of the symptoms produced by the mechanismof repression are clearly referable to one or other of thesevarieties. A simple example will render intelligible both thenature of the phenomena we are now considering, and thesubdivision which we are seeking to establish. In certainelderly unmarried women the 'sex complex' (including inthat term the various instincts belonging to sex) has beendenied its normal outlet and has ultimately become repressed.Under these circumstances the existence of the repressedcomplex may be evidenced by two groups of familiar pheno-mena. The resistance which forbids the normal expression ofthe complex may appear as an exaggerated prudery; thisclearly serves to conceal the objectionable complex fromconsciousness, and hence fulfils the function of a censure. Thecomplex will contrive, nevertheless, to express itself in someindirect manner, e.g. as a morbid interest in births, marriages,and scandals.

Phenomena due to indirect expression and those ascribableto the censure will, of course, generally occur together,

81

Page 95: The Psychology of Insanity

although in one case the first may be more prominent, inanother the second. For purposes of description, however, itwill be clearer to deal with the two groups separately, and weshall find it advantageous to commence with the considerationof the second group.

The essential character of the symptoms ascribable to thecensure is that they assist the process of resistance, and help inthe active repression of the objectionable complex. Availingourselves of the diagrams on p. 78, we may regard thesesymptoms as weights added to the repressing process repre-sented by R, which further guard against any appearance ofthe complex in the field of consciousness. In a large number ofcases they are of the type seen in the prudery example de-scribed above, the exaggerated appearance in the superficiallayers of the mind of the opposite quality to that belonging tothe complex in question. A familiar instance is the conceal-ment of diffidence and social shyness by the assumption of aboisterous good fellowship. In the sphere of insanity a similarmechanism accounts for some of the manic states describedin chapter in. In a case recorded by Dr Devine, for example,the patient was suffering from an incurable cancer. She was atfirst intensely depressed, tortured by the pain accompanyingthe disease, and filled with gloomy forebodings concerning thefuture of her husband and children. Later, however, signs ofexcitement appeared, and finally she passed into a typicalmanic state, which necessitated her removal to the mentalhospital. She was then abnormally joyous and elated, in con-stant movement, singing hymns and litanies, and apparentlyecstatically happy. She maintained that she was now perfectlywell, and that the disease had been completely cured. Thepsychological explanation of this case is obvious. The dis-tressing conflict between the hopeless facts and all the patient'smost cherished ambitions and desires, actually seen in the firstphase of the case, had been solved by a process of repression.The facts were shut out from consciousness, and the resistanceto their entry assisted by the development in consciousness ofthe abnormal gaiety and elation which characterised the

82

Page 96: The Psychology of Insanity

manic phase. A similar mechanism probably accounts for thecondition known as spes phthisica, the astonishing cheerfulnessand optimism which frequently characterises the last stages ofpulmonary consumption.

Another familiar manifestation of the censure is to be foundin the concealment of a gnawing sorrow by the assumption ofa witty exterior. It is a common observation that a secretunhappiness often lurks beneath the sparkling witticisms ofthe man of jokes. Humour is, indeed, one of the great refugesof life, and the man who is sensitive but has no humour suffersmuch from the bitterness of experience. By the aid of humour,experience which is unpalatable can be deprived of its realsignificance and treated as a joke, and thus we may be savedthe sting of many a painful conflict. The extension of thisprinciple into the field of abnormal psychology is perhapsbest seen in the * drunkard's humour', which is so characteristica feature of the chronic alcoholic. Here we find a superficialwit, consisting essentially in an inability to take anythingseriously, even the gravest facts of life. The consequences of hisvice, poverty, a wrecked career, the miseries of wife andchildren, are glossed over by the alcoholic with a pleasantryor a bon mot, and are not allowed to disturb his exaggeratedself-complacency. In this manner he achieves a superficialpeace of mind, and is saved from that remorse which consti-tutes the most distressing of all conflicts.

The repression of a painful complex by the exaggerateddevelopment in consciousness of the opposite quality will alsoenable us to understand the genesis of some obsessions. Thefollowing example will serve as a minor illustration of thisprocess. A man who had been addicted in his boyhood to thethieving of small sums of money, developed in later lifean exaggerated honesty. He would devote endless time andtrouble to the payment of some trifling excess fare, and anundischarged debt was a source of unceasing worry and self-reproach. The explanation of this abnormal rectitude isevidently to be found in the mechanism we are now consider-ing. The memory of his early lapses constituted a painful

83

Page 97: The Psychology of Insanity

complex intensely repugnant to the man's adult consciousness.He therefore strove to banish it from his mind, and to concealits presence by the exaggerated assumption of the opposingquality. It will be remembered that in chapter in this over-weighting of a particular element in consciousness wasdescribed as the essential character which defines an obsession.Such obsessions may in some cases be so persistent andpronounced as altogether to upset the mental stability of theindividual, so that his behaviour becomes definitely abnormal.A common example is 'washing mania', an irresistible desireto wash the hands at every moment of the day, with an over-whelming fear of dirt and contamination. This is often foundwhere some morally objectionable habit is present whicharouses constant remorse in the mind of the patient. Thepersonality reacts to the complex, which it regards as morallyunclean, by the symbolical assumption of an over-conscientiousand exaggerated cleanliness.

In the majority of the examples hitherto considered thecensure has manifested itself by the exaggerated developmentin consciousness of a quality which is the reverse of that presentin the offending complex. It is not necessary, however, thatthe quality developed should always have this oppositecharacter. Provided that it serves to conceal the complex itwill efficiently carry out the repressing function for which it hasbeen created. Cynicism, for instance, by which the individualendeavours to persuade himself that the complex or the forceswhich oppose it are worthless and unreal, is a common methodof dealing with the insoluble conflicts of life. The artificialelation produced by alcohol, opium, and some other drugs,serves a similar purpose. The submerging of conflicts is, indeed,the chief object for which these drugs are taken, and this basicfact must be taken into account in any efficient attempt todeal with the alcohol question. It has been well said that

almost universally regarded as either, on the one hand, asin or a vice, or, on the other hand, as a disease, there can belittle doubt that it [alcoholism] is essentially a response to apsychological necessity. In the tragic conflict between what he

Page 98: The Psychology of Insanity

has been taught to desire and what he is allowed to get, manhas found in alcohol, as he has found in certain other drugs,a sinister but effective peacemaker, a means of securing, forhowever short a time, some way out of the prison-house ofreality back to the Golden Age.1

Another way in which the resistance offered by conscious-ness to an offending complex may manifest itself, is by theassumption of some feverish activity, whose object is so to fillthe field of consciousness with other ideas and activities thatthe repressed complex cannot make any appearance. A case inpoint is provided by the disappointed man who devotes himselfto some strenuous sport or profession in order, as commonlanguage aptly expresses it, ' to drive his troubles from hismind'. A minor example of the same mechanism is often seenin everyday social life, when some subject peculiarly painfulto one of the individuals present is inadvertently introducedinto a general conversation. The individual may endeavourto conceal his perturbation by a rapid flow of remarks aboutsome other thing, a phenomenon which may be describedas a 'press of conversation'. A precisely similar mode of reac-tion, though more advanced in degree, accounts for certainsymptoms met with in the sphere of insanity. Thus thesymptom known as vorbeireden, a term which has been some-what clumsily rendered into English as ' talking past the point',is frequently encountered in cases where the patient possessessome complex which he is endeavouring to repress. The patientdoes not answer our questions but replies with some totallyirrelevant remarks, which are often grotesquely inappropriate,and give to his conversation a characteristic aspect of meaning-less incoherence. Thus one patient, in whose life a lady of thename of Green had played a very prominent part, replied tothe question 'Do you know a Miss Green?' with, 'Green,that's green, that's blue, would you say that water is blue?'Occasionally the patient dissects the question into its consti-tuent words or syllables, furnishing a string of irrelevant asso-ciations to each, and thereby avoiding any direct answer to

1 W. Trotter, Instincts of the Herd in Peace and War (London, 1916).

85 D

Page 99: The Psychology of Insanity

the question as a whole. Often it can be shown that a patientconverses normally except when a question which stimulatesthe hidden complex is given; his replies then exhibit thepeculiar incoherence just described. The explanation of thismode of reaction is, of course, that the repression is therebypreserved, and the stimulation is not allowed to exert itsnormal effect, the appearance in consciousness of the ideasbelonging to the complex.

The symptom known as 'mutism5, although apparentlydirectly opposite in character to the rapid flow of talk describedabove, often serves a precisely similar purpose. The patientpreserves a rigid silence, and our questions meet with no re-sponse whatever. Occasionally this phenomenon is generalised,as it were, so that for months at a time no word passes thepatient's lips.

We must now turn to the other group of phenomena causedby the presence of a repressed complex, those due to theindirect expression of the complex itself. Numerous exampleshave already been given in the earlier part of the presentchapter. We may now pass on, however, to consider instanceswhich exhibit this mechanism in a more pronounced form,and where the manifestations produced are more definitelyabnormal.

Certain compulsive actions belonging to the group ofobsessions may be mentioned here, of which an excellentexample is furnished by the case described on p. 36. It will beremembered that the patient in question suffered from anirresistible compulsion to examine the number of every bank-note which came into her hands. Now the genesis of this com-pulsion will be apparent so soon as we are acquainted withdetails of the patient's history which were revealed by apsychological analysis. Some time previously the lady hadfallen in love with a certain man whom she had met in acountry hotel. One day she asked him to change a coin for her.The man complied with her wish and, putting the coin in hispocket, remarked that he would not part with it. This episodearoused hopes in the lady's mind that her affections were

86

Page 100: The Psychology of Insanity

reciprocated, and she longed to know whether he would keephis word. Any money which came into her hands alwaysrecalled the scene in the hotel, and the emotions and desireswith which it was associated. The man finally departed, how-ever, without making any further advances, and ultimatelythe lady realised that the hopes she had entertained could haveno fruition. The conflict which thus arose was dealt with bya process of repression. The lady strove to banish the painfulchapter from her life and to forget that the desires associatedwith it had ever existed. The repression was successful, andthe complex was not permitted to make any appearance inconsciousness by way of the normal channels. The intenseinterest in money which passed through her hands persisted,however, affording a route by which the complex could obtainan indirect expression, and this indirect expression crystallisedinto that exaggerated preoccupation with the bank-notenumbers, which formed the dominant symptom of the case.

In all the instances of indirect expression which have hithertobeen considered it will be apparent that the essential featureof the process consists in the complex expressing itself along sodevious a route that it is enabled to avoid the resistance offeredby the censure. The mode of expression must be sufficientlyindirect to ensure that the real origin of the ideas appearingin consciousness is efficiently concealed from the individualhimself. That is to say, the repressed complex can only exertan influence upon consciousness provided that the influenceis distorted to a greater or less degree.

The various methods by which this necessary distortion maybe attained are exceedingly numerous, and have but little incommon beyond the one fundamental factor that they serveto conceal from consciousness the real origin of the ideasappearing in it. We have already become acquainted withmany of these methods, and the detailing of other varieties willform the subject of the remainder of this chapter, and of thewhole of the next. The mechanism of indirect expression has,indeed, an importance which cannot be over-estimated. Therecan be little doubt that a vast number of the symptoms of

87D*

Page 101: The Psychology of Insanity

insanity are explicable as instances of its action, and that in itis to be found the solution of the apparently incomprehensibleand senseless character which attaches to many of those symp-toms. The meaning of this general statement will become clearerat a later stage of our investigation, and it will be profitableto postpone its more detailed consideration until we haveaccumulated some further material.

One of the most important methods by which the distortionnecessary for the expression of a repressed complex is obtainedconsists in the employment of symbolism. For example, inelderly unmarried women the repressed maternal instinctsmay find a distorted outlet in an exaggerated affection fordogs and cats. The function of the symbolisation is obviouslythe concealing of the real causal ideas from the consciousnessof the individual. In everyday life feelings of self-importance,whose overt expression is forbidden by the traditions of socialconduct, frequently manifest themselves by the employment ofsymbolisms. We may cite such examples as affectations of gaitor dress, a pedantic phraseology, the adoption of a conversa-tion as polysyllabic as possible, and of a handwriting decoratedwith innumerable flourishes. In insanity symbolism plays aprominent part. The instances we have just considered appearin an exaggerated form as the stilted phraseology replete withneologisms, and other ludicrous affectations and mannerismsso frequently met with in the adolescent insane.

The mechanism of symbolisation accounts for many of thecurious phenomena known as 'stereotyped actions', of whichseveral examples were given in chapter in. We may select oneborrowed from Dr Jung. An old female patient, who had beenan inmate of the hospital for many years, spent her wholeexistence in the performance of a single stereotyped action.She had never been heard to speak, and she never exhibitedthe faintest interest in anything that went on around her.All day long she sat in a huddled position, continuouslymoving her arms and hands in a manner resembling the actionof a shoemaker who is engaged in sewing boots. During herwaking hours this movement absorbed her whole attention,

88

Page 102: The Psychology of Insanity

and it was carried out with unfailing regularity and monotonyfrom one year's end to another. When her history was investi-gated it was found that as a young girl she had been engagedto be married, and that the engagement had been suddenlybroken off. This event occasioned a great emotional shock,and she rapidly passed into the insane state which persistedthroughout the remainder of her life. It was further elicitedthat the faithless lover had been a shoemaker by trade.

Armed with these facts we can easily reconstruct the psycho-logical processes responsible for the symptoms which thepatient exhibited. The sudden termination of the engagementcaused a distressing conflict, which was finally solved by aprocess of repression. The affections and desires which hadplayed so important a part in the patient's mind were repressedon account of their incompatibility with the world of fact, andwere only allowed to appear in an indirect and distorted! form.This indirect expression was provided by the stereotypedaction which symbolised for the patient the whole system ofideas and emotions connected with her lost lover. The entiredetachment from the real world, the failure to react in anyway to her environment, and the other symptoms present inthis case will be better understood at a later stage of ourinquiry, and will be fully dealt with in a subsequent chapter(P- "5)-

A frequent method by which a repressed complex obtains anindirect expression is afforded by the mechanism known as'projection5. This method is so important, and appears in suchprotean forms, that it will be necessary to study it in somedetail, and the whole of the next chapter will therefore bedevoted to its consideration.

Page 103: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER IX

PROJECTION

IN the preceding chapter the phenomena produced by therepression of a complex were divided into two groups, thosedue to the indirect expression of the complex itself, and thosedue to the presence of a resistance or censure which preventsthe complex exercising its normal direct effect. In all theexamples hitherto considered the symptoms present couldwithout much difficulty be assigned to one or other of thesetwo groups. It will nevertheless be obvious that this distinctionis largely artificial, and that in the formation of each symptomthe factors of indirect expression and resistance both take part.The symptoms may be regarded, in fact, as a compromisebetween the two factors in question. The complex struggles toexpress itself, while the resistance endeavours to prevent itachieving its end. The symptom is finally evolved as a com-promise between the two opposing forces. In each of theexamples cited in the last chapter, however, one of the twocomponents seemed to play a preponderating part in thecompromise produced, so that the symptom could be classifiedas belonging to the corresponding group.

The group of symptoms to which we must now direct ourattention, those due to the mechanism of'projection5, exhibitthis preponderance of one component to a less marked degree,and the phenomena belonging to it are best regarded asinstances of compromise formation in which the parts playedby the two opposing forces are approximately equal.

4 Projection may be defined as a peculiar reaction of themind to the presence of a repressed complex, in which thecomplex or its effect is regarded by the personality as belongingno longer to itself, but as the production of some other realor imaginary individual. The meaning of this definition willbe made clear by the consideration of some simple examples

Page 104: The Psychology of Insanity

People who possess some fault or deficiency of which they areashamed are notoriously intolerant of that same fault or defi-ciency in others. Thus the parvenu who is secretly consciousof his own social deficiencies talks much of the c bounders' and* outsiders' whom he observes around him, while the one thingwhich the muddle-headed man cannot tolerate is a lack ofclear thinking in other people. In general it may be said thatwhenever one encounters an intense prejudice one may withsome probability suspect that the individual himself exhibitsthe fault in question or some closely similar fault. An excellentillustration of this mechanism is to be found in Hamlet, in theexcessive aversion with which the Player-Queen regards thepossibility of a second marriage, although a secret desire forsuch a marriage is already present in her mind.

The instances that second marriage moveAre base respects of thrift, but none of love . . .Nor earth to me give food, nor heaven light.Sport and repose lock from me day and night,To desperation turn my trust and hope,An anchor's cheer in prison be my scope,Each opposite that blanks the face of joyMeet what I would have well, and it destroy,Both here and hence pursue me lasting strife,If, once a widow, ever I be wife.

Shakespeare's acquaintance with the psychological mechan-ism we are considering is evidenced by the comment of thereal queen:

The lady doth protest too much, methinks.

We may express the psychological processes seen in thesecases as follows; the fault constitutes a complex which isrepugnant to the personality as a whole, and its presencewould therefore naturally lead to that particular form ofconflict which is known as self-reproach. The personalityavoids this conflict, however, by 'projecting' the offendingcomplex on to some other person, where it can be efficientlyrebuked without that painful emotion which inevitably

Page 105: The Psychology of Insanity

accompanies the recognition of deficiencies in ourselves. Thatis to say, the personality reacts to the repugnant complex byexaggeratedly reproaching the same facts in other people,thereby concealing the skeleton in its own cupboard. Themore comfortable expedient of rebuking one's neighbour issubstituted for the unpleasant experience of self-reproach.The biological function served by projection is, therefore, thesame as in all other varieties of repression, the avoidance ofconflict and the attainment of a superficial peace of mind.

In the sphere of insanity the mechanism of projection playsa prominent part, and a great variety of symptoms may beascribed to its action. Alcoholism, described in the last chapteras one of humanity's refuges from the stress of conflict, providesmany excellent examples. The chronic alcoholic develops withgreat frequency delusions concerning the conduct of his wifeor other relatives. Thus one of my patients complained bitterlythat his wife was dissolute, a drunkard, and a spendthrift, thatshe neglected both himself and the children, and that sheallowed the home to go to rack and ruin. Investigation showed,however, that all these ideas were purely delusional, andwithout foundation in fact. The patient himself was the realculprit, and each statement that he made was true of himselfbut not of his wife. The psychological explanation of hisdelusions is to be found in the mechanism of projection. By itsaid the patient's personality was enabled to treat the objection-able complex as an entire stranger for whom it was in no senseresponsible, and thereby to substitute an illusory self-com-placency for the pangs of remorse. In such cases as these alco-holism has indeed achieved its aim, and freedom from conflicthas been attained, but only at the price of mental integrityand self-honesty, and the mental hospital has become theinevitable consequence.

Many so-called ' delusions of persecution' may be similarlyexplained by the mechanism of projection. The patient hassome secret desire which is repugnant to the personality,perhaps because it is incompatible with the individual's generalprinciples or trends of thought. The mind, therefore refuses to

92

Page 106: The Psychology of Insanity

treat the desire as part of itself, and projects it into some otherreal or fictitious person, who then becomes an enemy striving toachieve the patient's downfall. In its minor degrees this mech-anism is to be seen in the excuses with which we frequentlyendeavour to mitigate our moral lapses. We will not acknow-ledge to ourselves that it was our own ambitions and desireswhich led to the commission of the fault, but seek to shift theblame to the shoulders of our neighbour. Through all ages* the woman tempted me' has been a stock excuse of erringman. This type of projection attains a much greater develop-ment, however, in certain varieties of insanity. In ' old maids'insanity', for example, an unmarried lady of considerableage, and of blameless reputation, begins to complain of theundesirable attentions to which she is subjected by some maleacquaintance. She explains that the man is obviously anxiousto marry her, and persistently follows her about. Finally,certain trifling incidents lead her to believe that he is schemingto abduct her by force, and on the strength of this she perhapswrites him an indignant letter, or lodges a complaint with thepolice. Investigation follows, and it is found not only that theman is entirely innocent of the charges levelled against him,but that he has never expressed the least interest in the lady,and is probably hardly aware of her existence. The lady iscertified to be suffering from 'delusions of persecution', andis removed to a hospital.

This by no means uncommon sequence of events can beeasily explained with the aid of the psychological laws now atour disposal. The patient's sex instincts have been allowed nonormal outlet, and have finally become sternly repressed,generally with an exaggerated development in consciousnessof the opposite quality. This latter, of course, constitutes theprudery so frequently observed in such cases, whose origin wehave studied in a former chapter. The repressed instinctsobtain an indirect expression, however, by the mechanism ofprojection. The desires originating therefrom are roused toactivity by the man in question, and the real state of affairsis that the lady is in love with the man but, owing to the

93

Page 107: The Psychology of Insanity

repression, the mind will not acknowledge that these ideas andemotions are part of itself, and finds a solution of the conflict byreversing the significance of the desires and projecting themupon their own object. The bearer of the repugnant complexhence appears to the personality as an unwelcome aggressor,and the genesis of the persecutory delusions is complete.

In many cases of delusions of persecution in which thedevelopment is closely similar to that just described, the desiresare projected into an individual who has no real existence.The patient's mind, in its struggle to obtain freedom from theinternal conflict, invents not only the man's conduct, but theman himself. This more complicated form of projection is ofcommon occurrence, and the female patient who indignantlycomplains of the violent wooing to which she is subjected bysome altogether imaginary man is to be found in every mentalhospital.

In another variety of projection it is not the complex itselfwhich is projected but the reproaches to which it gives rise.The biological purpose which this variety subserves is the sameas before, the avoidance of conflict. It is obvious that the pain-ful stress which accompanies self-reproach is obviated so longas the two opposing forces whose conflict produces it aredislocated from each other, and this dislocation may beequally well attained by projecting either of the two antagon-ists. In the variety we are now about to consider the patientno longer reproaches himself, but imagines that he is beingreproached by other people. The normal analogue of thisprocess is well known—the guilty conscience which sees theaccusing finger everywhere around. It is but a small stepfurther to the development of 'delusions of reference'. Thepatient is intensely suspicious; if two or three of his fellowsconverse together he imagines that he forms the subject of theremarks, the casual stranger becomes a designing enemy, untilfinally every trivial event is welded into one vast conspiracyto destroy him. In patients of this kind the development ofhallucinations is extremely common. The reproaches are notmerely construed into the actions of those about them, they

94

Page 108: The Psychology of Insanity

are handed over to altogether imaginary persecutors. Theportion of his mind which the personality has cut off anddeclined to acknowledge makes its reappearance as an hallu-cinatory voice. Thus one patient, whose mode of life hadwrecked both himself and his family, discussed his formerexperiences with revolting complacency. He complainedbitterly, however, of the system of persecution to which he wassubjected; people concealed themselves in the ceiling andunder his bed, and poured upon him a flood of abuse andthreats, which rendered existence almost insupportable.Hallucinations of this kind may be regarded as literal examplesof the 'small voice of conscience', distorted by repres-sion. It will be observed that such a patient has successfullyavoided the sting of remorse, but he has exchanged Scylla forCharybdis, and has sacrificed his mental integrity to obtainthe hardly more desirable alternative of a constant persecution.

In chapter iv it was pointed out that hallucinations, and thesystems of ideas which hallucinations express, are to be re-garded as dissociated portions of the patient's own conscious-ness. We are now in a position to understand why this dissocia-tion takes place. The systems of ideas in question are for onereason or another incompatible with the personality as awhole, and their appearance in consciousness would in theordinary course of events give rise to conflict and painfulstress. To avoid this conflict repression has been called intoplay, and the repressed complexes can only obtain theindirect expression afforded by projection. The phenomenadue to the projection are hence dislocated from the personality,and make their appearance as dissociated systems.

95

Page 109: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER X

THE IRRATIONALITY OF THE INSANE

T H E attribute of the insane patient which is at once the mostgeneral, the most obvious, and the most striking, is his apparentirrationality. It is so evident that the delusions he exhibits arefalse beliefs, that the hallucinations have no objective reality,that the depression or exaltation is totally unjustified by theactual state of affairs. He is, moreover, so plainly imperviousto the contradictions which his experience everywhere pre-sents to him, and so absurdly obtuse to every argument anddemonstration which our wits can devise. In the face of all thisthe superficial observer can only conclude that the root of theevil lies in the patient's incapacity to see reason, and that thesegrotesque symptoms have arisen simply because the mind haslost its ability to think rationally. To such an observer theessence of the matter is that the reasoning powers are diseased,and hence that the mind is capable of thinking any thought,however absurd and baseless it may be.

A more careful investigation, however, soon reveals factswhich it is difficult to reconcile with this view. In manypatients the reasoning powers seem to be in excellent order solong as they are applied to matters not immediately connectedwith the delusional system. Thus a patient who is firmlyconvinced that he is the son of George III may be capable ofsolving the most abstruse mathematical problems, and mayperhaps fulfil duties in the hospital which demand the utmostnicety of judgment and discrimination. Are we to assume thatin such a case the reasoning powers act normally and efficientlyso long as the question of the patient's ancestry is not touchedupon, but that they then suddenly become diseased and useless,so that the mind is permitted to weave ludicrous ideas withoutbeing called to account at the bar of reason? Or are we toconclude that the theory of the superficial observer is not

96

Page 110: The Psychology of Insanity

applicable, and that the fault does not lie in a disease of thereasoning powers?

A consideration of the results reached in the precedingchapters of this book enables us at once to decide in favour ofthe second alternative. The origin of the abnormal mentalprocesses is not to be found in any disturbance of the reasoningpowers per se, but in the material which is presented to thosepowers. The patient does not believe that he is the son ofGeorge III because he has lost the capacity to reason, butbecause the proposition is presented to his mind in a lightwhich makes it the only plausible and rational conclusionpossible. He is only apparently irrational, because theobserver does not see the chain of mental processes whichhave produced the result, but only the result itself, standing asan isolated phenomenon without obvious basis or justification.

The apparent absurdity of the delusion rests on the fact thatit is the indirect expression of some other mental process whichis itself hidden from view. This other process is intelligible andunderstandable enough, once it has been elicited. So long as itremains hidden, however, the delusion must inevitably appearto be a structure without foundation, and without relation tothings as they are. The analyses contained in precedingchapters will all serve to illustrate the truth of this proposition.We found that in every case the incomprehensibility of thedelusion disappeared so soon as we unearthed the chain ofmental processes actually responsible for it, just as the manwho falls into a passion over some trifle is incomprehensibleonly until we discover that his rage is really the result of someother and quite adequate cause.

We can understand, moreover, the well-known fact that it isuseless to argue with the insane patient concerning his delu-sions. As our arguments will be directed, not against thehidden real cause of the delusion; but merely against its super-ficial manifestation, they will obviously be ineffective. Theironly result will be to stimulate the patient to produce ' ration-alisations', endeavours to establish illusory logical props for astructure which is really built upon the underlying complex.

97 E

Page 111: The Psychology of Insanity

This method of dealing with arguments is not peculiar to theinsane. Examples of its employment are to be seen everywherearound us, and it has become proverbial in the couplet—

A man convinced against his willIs of the same opinion still.

Translated into technical language this would read: ' I t maybe possible by argument to show that each rationalisationwhich the man produces is logically untenable, until finally hecan produce no more—but as the complex really responsiblefor his position has not been attacked at all, it continues toproduce its effect, and the man remains of the same opinion.'The futility of logic as a weapon against the products of acomplex is notorious. No one imagines that it is possible toalter the convictions of a zealous party politician or sectarianby the process of arguing with him. For precisely the samereasons no psychiatrist imagines that argument is of any availagainst the delusions of the insane. In both cases the individualbecomes credulous or blind, according as the arguments pro-duced agree or conflict with the trend of the underlyingcomplex.

If we are called upon to explain the imperviousness toargument of the enthusiastic party politician or sectarian, wedo not assume that it is dependent upon a disease of thereasoning powers. Yet it is obvious that the mental processesin question are non-rational in the sense that they do notsatisfy the laws of logic. The conclusions of the politician arenot reached by impartially weighing the evidence before him;each step in his thinking is not the logical result of that whichhas preceded it. On the contrary, the conclusion is determinedby the ' political-complex' present, and the evidence may be suchthat an unbiased application of logical principles would leadto a diametrically opposite result. We are forced to conclude,therefore, that in the domain where his 'political-complex'holds sway, the politician does not always think ration-ally, because his reasoning powers are not allowed free play.But he does not himself realise that his thoughts are logically

98

Page 112: The Psychology of Insanity

vulnerable; they appear to him as propositions whose truthis at once obvious and beyond question, and he cannot under-stand how any other observer in possession of the same factscan possibly arrive at a different conclusion. 'To the Conser-vative, the amazing thing about the Liberal is his incapacityto see reason and accept the only possible solution of publicproblems.'1

The facts contained in the preceding paragraphs suggestfurther considerations which will enable us not only to cor-relate more exactly the mental processes of the insane with thoseoccurring in normal men, but also to obtain an insight intothe subjective aspect of the insane mind, that is to say, aninsight into the abnormal mental processes as they appear tothe patient himself.

There are, as a matter of fact, a large number of processesin the normal mind which possess those two characters, a non-rational origin and an immediate subjective obviousness, whichare apparent in the case of the party politician or sectarian.The simplest instances are to be found in the thoughts andactions which are the direct result of the primary instincts,more particularly those of self-preservation, nutrition, andsex. William James says of them:

Science may come and consider these ways, and find thatmost of them are useful. But it is not for the sake of their utilitythat they are followed, but because at the moment of followingthem we feel that that is the only appropriate and naturalthing to do. Not one rr^an in a billion, when taking his dinner,ever thinks of utility. He eats because the food tastes good andmakes him want more. If you ask him why he should want toeat more of what tastes like that, instead of revering you as aphilosopher he will probably laugh at you for a fool. Theconnection between the savoury sensation and the act itawakens is for him absolute and selbstverstdndlich, an a priorisynthesis of the most perfect sort, needing no proof but its ownevidence. . . . To the metaphysician alone can such questionsoccur as: Why do we smile, when pleased, and not scowl?Why are we unable to talk to a crowd as we talk to a single

1 W. Trotter, Instincts of the Herd in Peace and War (London, 1916).

99

Page 113: The Psychology of Insanity

friend? Why does a particular maiden turn our wits so upsidedown? The common man can only say, 'ofcourse we smile, ofcourse our heart palpitates at the sight of a crowd, of course welove the maiden, that beautiful soul clad in that perfect form,so palpably and flagrantly made from all eternity to be loved!'And so probably does each animal feel about the particularthings it tends to do in presence of particular objects. . . . Tothe broody hen the notion would probably seem monstrousthat there should be a creature in the world to whom a nestfulof eggs was not the utterly fascinating and precious and never-to-be-too-much-sat-upon object it is to her.

Trotter, in the extremely suggestive and stimulating articlesupon 'Herd Instinct', from which we have quoted above, hasshown that there is a vast group of mental processes possessingthis same subjective aspect, although they do not arise fromthe three instincts commonly designated as primary. Theassumptions, for example, 'upon which is based the bulk ofopinion in matters of Church and State, the family, justice,probity, honour, purity, crime, and so forth' are characterisedby this introspectual quality of the 'a priori synthesis of themost perfect sort'. Trotter demonstrates that these are all theresult of a fourth instinct, whose manifestations are of funda-mental importance in the psychology of gregarious animals,and to which he gives the name of 'herd instinct'.1 Herdinstinct ensures that the behaviour of the individual shall be inharmony with that of the community as a whole. Owing to itsaction each individual tends to accept without question thebeliefs which are current in his class, and to carry out withunthinking obedience the rules of conduct upon which theherd has set its sanction. For the average man herd instinctis the force which determines his ethical code and all thosebeliefs and opinions which are not the result of a specialknowledge. He carries out certain rules of life because his

1 The psychoanalytical school does not accept Trotter's ' herd instinct' asa psychological entity, but regards it as a biological conception which doesnot correspond to any factor capable of being elicited by psychologicalanalysis. According to this school, the phenomena which Trotter explainsby herd instinct are the product of other instinctive forces, particularlythose concerned in the relation of the developing individual to his parents.

IOO

Page 114: The Psychology of Insanity

fellow-men carry out these same rules; he believes certainthings because he lives in an environment where those thingsare believed by everyone around him. If he is asked to explainhis conduct or his opinions, he will, of course, at once producerationalisations of the type we have described in chapter vand will persuade himself that these rationalisations are theactual causes of his behaviour. But in reality the causes respon-sible for his behaviour are, first, the fact that other peoplebehave in that way, and secondly, the operation of herd in-stinct. The rationalisation is produced subsequently, andsimply because man has an overwhelming need to believe thathe is acting upon rational grounds.

If we examine the mental furniture of the average man, weshall find it made up of a vast number of judgments of a veryprecise kind upon subjects of very great variety, complexity,and difficulty. He will have fairly settled views upon the originand nature of the universe, and upon what he will probablycall its meaning; he will have conclusions as to what is tohappen to him at death and after, as to what is and whatshould be the basis of conduct. He will know how the countryshould be governed, and why it is going to the dogs; why thispiece of legislation is good, and that bad. He will have strongviews upon military and naval strategy, the principles of taxa-tion, the use of alcohol and vaccination, the treatment ofinfluenza, the prevention of hydrophobia, upon municipaltrading, the teaching of Greek, upon what is permissible in art,satisfactory in literature, and hopeful in science.

The bulk of such opinions must necessarily be withoutrational basis, since many of them are concerned with prob-lems admitted by the expert to be still unsolved, while as tothe rest it is clear that the training and experience of no averageman can qualify him to have any opinion upon them at all.The rational method adequately used would have told himthat on the great majority of these questions there could be forhim but one attitude—that of suspended judgment.1

All these non-rational opinions and beliefs appear to theirpossessor as propositions whose truth is immediately obvious,and whose validity it is silly to question or to doubt. They are

1 W. Trotter, Instincts of the Herd in Peace and War (London, 1916).

IOI

Page 115: The Psychology of Insanity

held, moreover, with a peculiar emotional warmth andinstinctive certainty, which it is difficult to define, but whosecharacter will be at once appreciated by anyone with areasonable capacity for self-introspection. Genuine knowledge,the product of a scientific deduction from observed facts,appears in quite other guise than this. It is relatively cold, anddevoid of the warmth which accompanies non-rational beliefs.If its truth is called in question we are not annoyed, but aremerely stimulated to examine with renewed attention thefoundations upon which it rests. The distinction between thetwo classes of mental process will be immediately apparentto the reader if he will compare, as regards their introspectiveaspect, his views upon the proposition that a man who ill-treatsa woman is a cad, with his attitude to the proposition that theearth goes round the sun.

If these facts are considered in the light of the principlesenunciated in foregoing chapters we shall easily recognise thatnon-rational beliefs and opinions are the product of complexes,and that the peculiar warmth we have described is the emo-tional tone which invariably accompanies the action of acomplex. If we argue with the holder of such beliefs the com-plex will protect itself by one of two defensive reactions.Either the arguments will be rejected as senseless or wicked, ora flood of rationalisations will be produced which invest thebelief with a plausibility entirely satisfactory to their creator.

Now these are precisely the characters which have beenshown to exist in the delusions of the insane. They also havea non-rational origin, and are in reality the product of com-plexes. They also are accompanied by a peculiar emotionalwarmth, and a feeling of instinctive certainty. Moreover, theyhave to the patient himself just that same character of imme-diate obviousness and unquestionable truth, so that he cannotunderstand how we can fail to see how absolutely justifiablehis contentions are, and how all the evidence makes the con-clusions he has reached the only ones possible or conceivable.

This latter statement contains the answer to the problemposed upon a former page, the problem of representing to

102

Page 116: The Psychology of Insanity

ourselves the subjective aspect of a delusion, the light in whichthe delusion must appear to the patient who possesses it. Itappears as an obvious proposition, which none but the perversecan doubt, and which is so patently true that to attack it is onlyunprofitably silly or wicked.

We must therefore conclude that the insane patient is notirrational in the sense that his reasoning powers are in them-selves different from those of normal men. It is true thatcertain of his mental processes have a non-rational origin, butit is equally true that the great bulk of opinions and beliefsheld by the normal man arise in a similar way, and we cannottherefore on this account attribute a peculiar irrationality tothe insane.

We are therefore faced with a further problem. If the positiontaken up in this chapter is correct, and if irrationality is notthe hall-mark of insanity, what are the essential characterswhich distinguish the insane from the normal man? It mustbe confessed that in the present state of knowledge we can offerno completely satisfactory answer to this question, but ourfailure is due, in part at least, to the indefinite and almostmeaningless nature of the problem presented to us. The termsemployed therein have no precise significance, and of suchterms it is obviously impossible to predicate any essentialcharacters whatever. Insanity is not a definite entity likescarlet fever or tuberculosis, but it is used to denote a hetero-geneous group of phenomena which have but little in common.Moreover, its boundaries have varied from age to age accord-ing to the dominating conceptions of the period, and it will beremembered that in chapter i we saw that individuals who inmedieval times were regarded with esteem and reverencewould now be removed without hesitation to a mental hospital.

All this being taken into account, the only solution of theproblem which it seems feasible to offer consists in the mereenumeration of certain vague distinctions. No single one canbe regarded as essential, but, taken in their entirety, theyserve roughly to mark off the sphere of insanity from that ofsanity.

103

Page 117: The Psychology of Insanity

The first criterion depends upon the degree in which thephenomena are manifested. We have endeavoured to demon-strate in preceding chapters that the symptoms of insanity arethe result of psychological mechanisms which are identicalwith those found in the normal mind. In the former, however,the processes are carried to a more advanced stage, and beyondthe limits which are generally regarded as normal. Thus theincompetent workman who ascribes his failure to the inferiorityof his tools and the unfair treatment meted out to him by hisemployer is admittedly still sane, while the man who complainsto the police that he is the victim of an organised boycott iscertified to be suffering from ' delusions of persecution' and isremoved to a hospital. In both cases the psychological mech-anism is the same, but in the latter the process has been carriedfurther.

Closely connected with this exaggeration which forms ourfirst criterion is the second, and probably the most important,distinction between insanity and sanity, the distinction ofconduct. The conduct of the insane is generally anti-social, andit is this criterion, expressed in the legal definition * dangerousto himself or others', which in most cases determines whetheror not the patient shall be sent to a mental hospital. The anti-social attribute which generally belongs to insane conduct maybe positive or negative in character. Thus a patient may havepersecutory delusions which make him an actual danger to hisfellows, or which lead him to take his own life. On the otherhand his behaviour may be anti-social in the sense that he isincapable of efficiently taking part in the social machine, as inthe variety of insanity which we have termed 'emotionaldementia'.

Other criteria depend upon the character of the psycho-logical mechanisms responsible for the symptoms present. Wehave seen that many mental processes commonly met with ineveryday life, as well as certain symptoms definitely regardedas insane, are due to the indirect manifestations of repressedcomplexes. In the latter group, however, the complex expres-sion is generally more indirect, and therefore more distorted.

104

Page 118: The Psychology of Insanity

Associated with this is the further distinction that the ration-alisations produced in the insane cases are as a rule moreobvious and less plausible than those observed in everyday life.

The delusions of the insane resemble many of the beliefsand opinions held by the sane in the fact that in both cases themental processes have a non-rational origin. In other respects,however, they differ to such an extent that it is generally easyto decide to which of the two groups a given symptom mustbe assigned. The beliefs of the sane, whether true or false, aregenerally supported by the opinion of a class, and are the resultof the operation of herd instinct. The delusions of the insane,on the other hand, are not so supported, but are individualaberrations dependent upon factors working in direct opposi-tion to herd instinct. This latter distinction is of great impor-tance, and will be further considered in chapter xn. Thebeliefs of the sane, again, are often incompatible with facts,but no belief can be held for long which is very obviouslycontradicted by experience. For example, it is impossible for asane pauper to believe that he is a millionaire. In the insane,however, we have seen that this gross incompatibility withexperience is frequently observed. Moreover, although innormal men beliefs dependent upon strong emotional preju-dices are apparently insusceptible to argument and to any butthe most flagrant contradictions presented by actual exper-ience, yet this insusceptibility is not absolute. The opposingforces exert a slow erosive effect which in process of time pro-duces a gradual alteration in the belief, and perhaps ultimatelydestroys it. An insane delusion, however, seems altogetherfixed and immune to this action, and the processes describedonly serve to elaborate the defences with which it is hedgedround. All these latter distinctions depend upon the cardinalfactor of dissociation. In the insane dissociation has beencarried to a degree which is incompatible with normal thoughtor behaviour, and mental processes are allowed to pursuetheir course altogether undisturbed by the contradictionspresented by the facts of experience.

105

Page 119: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER XI

PHANTASY

T H E normal effect of a complex is to produce action. A trainof activity is set in motion whose goal is the realisation of thedesires and tendencies constituting the driving force of thecomplex. The complex finds a complete expression in theachieving of its ends. There is, however, another mode ofexpression by which satisfaction is often obtained, althoughthat satisfaction is only partial and limited. This second modeof expression is the construction of phantasy. In phantasy—or,to use the more widely known term, day-dreaming—we do notseek to satisfy our complexes in the world of reality, butcontent ourselves with the building of pleasant mental picturesin which the complexes attain an imaginary fulfilment.

The distinction between these two modes, the direct andcomplete expression in action, and the partial expression inphantasy, may be clearly seen in the effects produced by theso-called 'self-assertion complexes'. By the self-assertioncomplexes we mean those tendencies to aggrandisement of theself and the achieving of distinction amongst one's fellowswhich may be roughly grouped together under the heading of'ambition'. Their normal direct effect is to be seen in theindividual's struggle to get on, and to obtain a position whichwill ensure to him the respect and admiration of others. Inaddition to the direct expression in action, however, thesecomplexes may expend a variable portion of their energy inthe construction of phantasy. The phantasy produced in thisway constitutes the common phenomenon of'day-dreaming',which, although it occurs at every age, attains its most luxuriantdevelopment during adolescence. At this period the youngman will often revel in astonishing feats of the imagination,fascinating scenes of great deeds and applauding crowds, inwhich, of course, he invariably plays the part of the hero.

106

Page 120: The Psychology of Insanity

In the construction of this imagery the complexes we havementioned are assisted by the sex complexes, and the effectsof the two causal groups are closely intermingled. The greatdeeds are generally performed before the admiring eyes of somefair lady whose favour the hero covets.

We do not hear much about these day-dreams, because theirauthor is generally rather ashamed of his creations; in otherwords, they are subjected to a certain degree of that repressionwe have formerly described. Unless they are kept withinreasonable bounds their influence must, indeed, be regardedas harmful, because the energy of the complexes is expendedin the weaving of phantasies, and is not translated into action.This is the thought which underlies the following remarks ofWilliam James:

The weeping of a Russian lady over the fictitious personagesin the play, while her coachman is freezing to death on his seatoutside, is the sort of thing that everywhere happens on a lessglaring scale. Even the habit of excessive indulgence in music,for those who are neither performers themselves nor musicallygifted enough to take it in a purely intellectual way, has pro-bably a relaxing effect upon the character. One becomes filledwith emotions which habitually pass without prompting to anydeed, and so the inertly sentimental condition is kept up. Theremedy would be, never to suffer oneself to have an emotion ata concert without expressing it afterwards in some actual way.Let the expression be the least thing in the world—speakinggenially to one's aunt, or giving up one's seat in a horse-car, ifnothing more heroic offers—but let it not fail to take place.

The possibly pernicious effect of day-dreaming is seen evenbetter when it is employed as a refuge, so to speak, from reality.If the young man we have described, in his efforts to make acareer and to achieve distinction, experiences rebuffs andfailures, he may be induced to allow his complexes to expressthemselves by the construction of phantasies rather than by thesterner struggle to alter facts. He may console himself bypleasant dreams in which he marches to imaginary victories,while his enemies bow the knee in envious admiration. He maylive for a time in so attractive a world that he finds it hard to

107

Page 121: The Psychology of Insanity

drag himself back into relation with things as they are. In ourtechnical language we should say that he finds the complexincompatible with his actual environment, that there is a con-flict between the complex and reality. He compromises withthe difficulty by making no further attempts to combine thetwo opposing forces, but gives up the struggle with life, andretires temporarily into a world of the imagination where thecomplex works its will without colliding against brutal facts.

This phenomenon is extremely common, and most of us atone time or another console ourselves for the failure of ourambitions in the real world by the creation of these pleasantfancies. But a path opens here which leads us easily across thebridge into the regions of insanity, and the processes justconsidered provide a key to the interpretation of many of thesymptoms which we observe in the mental hospital.

In the normal cases the individual is aware that he is day-dreaming, and does not altogether lose touch with the realworld. His friends observe that he is 'absent-minded' andabsorbed in his own ideas, and that he takes no notice of whatgoes on around him. But he is able if necessary to drag himselfback into relation with the actual environment, although to doso often requires an appreciable effort. In other words, he isdissociated to some extent from the realities of everyday life,but this dissociation is only partial, incomplete, and temporary.If, however, the process assumes proportions which are defin-itely morbid, this dissociation becomes more pronouncedand permanent. The patient, as he may now be called,separates himself altogether from the real world and devotesall his mental energy to day-dreaming. He lives permanentlyin a self-made world where all the desires and ambitionsbelonging to the complex are luxuriantly fulfilled. Thismechanism is responsible for the symptoms observed in twotypes of insanity which, although closely allied to one another,may be roughly separated for descriptive purposes.

The first type, which may be regarded as an exaggeration ofnormal day-dreaming, comprises a number of those casesgrouped in chapter in under the heading of 'emotional

108

Page 122: The Psychology of Insanity

dementia'. The patient has apparently lost all interest in life;he expresses no desires or ambitions, makes no effort to employhimself in any way, and sits from day to day in the same cornerof the ward, inert and lethargic. His face is vacant andexpressionless, and he seems oblivious of everything whichtakes place around him. If he is addressed he will perhapsvouchsafe a monosyllabic reply, but it is impossible to rousehim from his apathy, and he will receive the news of hisparents' deaths with the same untroubled equanimity withwhich he eats his dinner. To the casual observer such a patientappears to have lost all mental activity, but, if we examine hismind more closely and look below its congealed surface, wefind that activity still exists, although it is diverted into chan-nels which lead to no external manifestation or practical result.All the available energy is absorbed in the construction ofpleasant phantasies of the kind we have described. The patienthas retired altogether into a world of day-dreams, and for himthe facts of real life have lost all significance and interest.

In the second type the patient has immersed himself in hisimaginary world even more completely and efficiently. Thephantasy created by his own mind acquires the tang of actualreality: he believes that he is the conquering hero or the multi-millionaire, and that the pleasant pictures he once imaginedhave become the facts of life. He has crossed the barrier whichseparates in the normal man day-dreams from the dreams thataccompany sleep, and the creations of an idle fancy havebecome the delusions of insanity. A further degree of dissocia-tion has been attained, and the complexes achieve a luxuriantexpression undisturbed by the flagrant contradictions whichexperience everywhere presents to them.

This mechanism, which has been termed 'wish fulfilment',furnishes a psychological interpretation for a vast number ofthe manifestations of insanity. One of the simplest examples ofits action is seen in the so-called 'betrothal-delirium', occa-sionally to be observed in women who have been jilted. All thedesires and ambitions which hitherto formed the kernel of thepatient's life have suddenly become incompatible with reality.

109

Page 123: The Psychology of Insanity

Out of the intense emotional stress engendered by this conflicta condition of insanity develops, characterised by a dream-like delirium in which the frustrated complexes attain animaginary fulfilment. In this delirium the patient believesthat she has been reconciled to her lover, preparations for thewedding are in progress, the bridegroom arrives, the marriageceremony takes place, and the dream-state is prolongedindefinitely in pictures of a subsequent wedded life, each ofwhich is lived through with all the intensity of reality.

In other cases the symptoms are less dramatic in character,but essentially similar in their mode of origin. A system ofmorbid mental processes develops in which the complexes thathave been denied expression in the world of reality obtain adelusional fulfilment. The patient believes that the defaultinglover has returned to his allegiance, or perhaps that she hasactually become his wife. The obvious inconsistency of suchbeliefs with the real facts of life is glossed over by the produc-tion of suitable rationalisations, and the development of thosesecondary delusions which have already been described onp. 71.

A similar mechanism accounts for those complicated andfantastic delusional systems which characterise a large percen-tage of the cases met with in the chronic wards of the hospital.Thus one of my patients announces that she is descended fromQueen Elizabeth, and is herself the rightful queen of England.She has been given the title of ' Rule Britannia', has severalarmies under her control, and is at the moment engaged inissuing orders to her generals to make a combined attack uponall the nations of Europe. She complains bitterly, however,that her movements are hampered by a conspiracy directed by'Mr Guelph', who has succeeded in obtaining her incarcer-ation in an asylum, and who strives to rob her of all theprivileges which belong to her rank.

This patient, prior to the outbreak of her insanity, was ahard-working woman of the servant class, whose life hadcontained little but a constant succession of hardships. In thegrandiose delusions which she exhibits, the day-dreams of the

n o

Page 124: The Psychology of Insanity

class that thrives on cheap romantic literature may easily berecognised, now elevated by a process of dissociation to therank of an actual belief, and pursuing their course in a logic-tight compartment secure from the contradiction of facts.Protected in this way from the controlling influence of realexperience, the self-assertion complexes strive to achieve aluxuriant expression by the production of constantly elabor-ated phantasies of grandeur. The persecutory ideas concerningthe conspiracy, on the other hand, are to be regarded as thesecondary delusions which generally arise in such cases asprocesses of rationalisation.

In all these cases the final outbreak of insanity occurs as thesolution of a conflict. The patient is unable to achieve hisambitions, either because the environment opposes insur-mountable obstacles or because his capacities are not equal tohis desires—in other words, there is a conflict between thecomplex and reality. This conflict is avoided by allowing thecomplex to obtain a partial expression by the construction ofphantasy, while the incompatibility of the real world is maskedby the production of the requisite degree of dissociation. Undersuch circumstances it might be said that reality is repressed,while the complex plays unchecked upon the surface ofconsciousness.

There is, however, another method by which conflict may beavoided in these cases, equally morbid in its character andeffects. If the patient finds that the complex cannot be satis-fied in the world of reality he may endeavour to banish italtogether from his life, to forget that he has ever experiencedthose particular desires, and to behave as if they had neverexisted. In other words he remains in touch with reality, andstrives to repress the complex.

These two methods of dealing with an intolerable conflictfrequently occur in the same patient, and both are well illus-trated in the following case, originally described by Jung.1

A man of between thirty and forty years of age, of excep-tional intelligence, and an archaeologist of note, was brought

1 C. G. Jung, Der Inhalt der Psychose (Vienna, 1908).

I l l

Page 125: The Psychology of Insanity

to the hospital in a condition of acute maniacal excitement.He was of short stature, thin and weakly, and he stutteredabominably. His history was as follows: He had been an intel-lectually precocious boy, and had early devoted himself to thestudy of archaeology, finishing his education at the Universityof B . At the conclusion of his university career he buriedhimself altogether in the pursuit of science, cut himself offmore and more from the world and from his friends, andfinally led the life of a complete hermit. Some years later,while on a holiday tour, he returned to B , where he spentmost of his days in long walks among the outskirts of the town.After one of these excursions he complained of feeling nervousand restless. A state of excitement developed, passing rapidlyinto the acute delirium which led to his removal to thehospital. On admission he was intensely confused, had no ideawhere he was, and spoke only in short sentences which nobodyunderstood. Periods of violent excitement were often present,during which he attacked all those about him, and could onlybe restrained by the united efforts of several attendants.Gradually the delirium abated, and one day the patient sud-denly awoke as if from a long dream, rapidly returned to hisnormal condition, and was shortly afterwards dischargedfrom the institution. He immediately resumed his former life,and in the following year produced several works of the firstrank. His acquaintances only observed that he seemed moreof a misanthrope and more of a hermit than ever. Then onceagain he came to B , and again occupied his days in longwalks. A fainting attack in the street was followed by an out-break of delirium, and for the second time he was brought tothe hospital. On this occasion, however, the symptoms weredifferent from those noted during his former illness. He per-formed complicated gymnastics all over the room, spoke of hismarvellous muscular power and bodily beauty, announcedhimself to be a great singer, and continually sang love ditties ofhis own composition. After a time the delirium lessened, hebecame more accessible, and it was possible for Dr Jung toundertake an analysis of the case.

112

Page 126: The Psychology of Insanity

If we now study the patient's history in the light of the factsrevealed by that analysis, our understanding of the case willbe considerably increased. During the time when the patientwas a student in B he fell in love with a certain lady, andthey were in the habit of taking long walks in the neighbour-hood of the town. The shyness and feeling of shame of the stut-terer prevented him from declaring his passion, and, more-over, marriage was at that time a financial impossibility. Atthe end of his university career he left B , and never againsaw the lady. Shortly afterwards he heard that she had marriedsomebody else. Then he buried himself in his hermit's life, andstrove to forget; in other words, the complex, painful throughits incompatibility with reality, was repressed. We have seen,however, that, though a complex may be repressed, it does notthereby cease to exist. It disappears from consciousness, and isnot allowed to play its normal part in the thoughts and activityof the mind. But it persists underneath, as it were, and sooneror later it manifests itself by one of those indirect methodswhich we have dealt with in former chapters. This is whatactually occurred in the case we are describing.

We saw that after some years of strenuous work our patientreturned to the town of B , and that a few days later thefirst outbreak of delirium occurred. The explanation of thisdelirium is simple—the repressed complex had burst on to thesurface. The content of the patient's mind during the attackmay be described as follows: He found himself in the chaos ofa mighty dream; great battles were in progress, and he wasalways in the centre of the fight, performing prodigies of valourand leading the armies with marvellous skill, while the ladywatched and awaited him as the prize of victory. This was theperiod when he blindly attacked all those about him andstruggled furiously with his attendants. Then came the finalvictory—the bride approached, and he awoke once more toreality and the dull routine of his life. The complex was againrepressed.

It will be observed how closely the content of this deliriumresembles the ordinary adolescent day-dreaming which we

Page 127: The Psychology of Insanity

have previously described. The difference consists merely in adegree of dissociation which permits the complex to manifestitself in a definitely hallucinatory form, altogether cut loosefrom the control of the personality.

In the second attack, which, like the first, was precededby a visit to B , the course of events was somewhat different.The complexes which then manifested themselves, althoughobviously closely allied to the sex complex, were rather thosewhich had arisen as a result of his bodily infirmities. It will beremembered that he was stunted and unattractive, his musclesatrophied and weak, and that he stuttered abominably. He wasentirely unmusical, his voice was harsh, and he was incapableof singing a note in tune. All this formed part of a complex ofbodily shame, which we saw in action at the time he wascourting his lady. Coupled with it, of course, was the intensesecret desire that the defects could be removed. During thesecond attack of delirium this was the complex which emergedto the surface, with all its desires fictitiously fulfilled. He wasimmensely strong, and a gymnast of the first rank—hence thecomplicated antics he performed around the room. He wasthe greatest singer in the world, and a prodigious orator. Hepossessed, in fact, the corresponding virtue for every defectwhich reality had inflicted upon him.

The psychological interpretation of this case may thereforebe resumed as follows. The complex is incompatible withreality, and the patient gives up the attempt to reconcile thetwo. At intervals he abandons reality and plunges into thecomplex—or, as it has been expressed, he flies into the diseaseto obtain a refuge from reality. During the periods whichintervene between the outbreaks of delirium he adoptsanother method of solving the conflict. He preserves his graspon the external world and avoids the conflict by the processof repressing the complex. But this can only be done at the costof annihilating a whole segment of his emotional life, and hebecomes a misanthrope and a hermit.

In many chronic cases, as in the example described uponp. n o , these so-called periods of sanity, during which the

114

Page 128: The Psychology of Insanity

incompatible complex is successfully repressed, are absent.The patient retires altogether into the complex and livespermanently in a self-made world where all the desires andambitions belonging to the complex are luxuriantly fulfilled.Under such circumstances the complex frequently undergoesa process known as 'degradation'. The phraseology in whichit finds expression becomes more distorted and stereotyped,often degenerating into a meaningless hotch-potch of words,and the mental processes generated by the complex becomeconcentrically diminished. Finally, the whole mental life of thepatient consists, perhaps, in the performance of some singlestereotyped action representing the wreck of the old complex.The patient described on p. 88, who spent her whole existencein the sewing of an imaginary boot, furnishes an excellentexample of this terminal stage.

The degradation of speech and mental content proceedsaccording to fairly precise laws which have been laboriouslyinvestigated by Jung and his followers. Space does not permitof any further description of them here, but it may be said thatby their aid it is possible to show that even the most incoherentand apparently meaningless speech has nevertheless a definitesignificance, capable of being elucidated by psychologicalanalysis.

There is one further psychological process which may profit-ably be dealt with in the present chapter, as it is intimatelyrelated to the phantasy construction to which our attentionhas so far been devoted. This process, technically known as'identification', is of considerable importance, and in itsminor degrees is frequently manifested in normal mental life.It consists in identifying ourselves with another individual,either real or fictitious, so that we experience his joys, sorrows,and desires, as if they were our own. So long as the identifica-tion holds we feel that he is part of our personality, and that weare living part of our lives in him. Identification is frequentlyencountered in both normal and abnormal psychology—itincludes many of the phenomena generally grouped under theheading of'sympathy'. The meaning of the conception will be

Page 129: The Psychology of Insanity

made clearer by the consideration of some illustrative examples.One of the best instances is afforded by the reader of a second-rate romantic novel. The explanation of the interest which thistype of fiction arouses lies in the fact that the reader identifieshimself with the hero, lives with him through a series of aston-ishing adventures, falls in love with the heroine, and liveshappily ever afterwards. The novel, in fact, permits the readerto experience the fascinations of day-dreaming without thetrouble of constructing the imagery himself.

An even better example is presented by the audience of amelodrama. Everybody who has observed the gallery duringan entertainment of this kind is aware that its inmates areliving on the stage, and always, of course, in the part of thehero or heroine. The illusion of reality which attaches tothe play allows the day-dreaming to be conducted much moreefficiently than in the case of the novel—hence the greaterpopularity of the drama. It is because the audience insiststhat its day-dreaming should be catered for, that the play-wright is compelled to provide a liberal supply of peers,and to cast his scenes not too far from Mayfair.

If we rise higher in the scale of art and consider the first-ratenovel or play, we find the mechanism of identification still atwork, but appearing now in a less simple form. The reader nolonger identifies himself merely with the hero, but rather withall the characters at once. He finds portrayed the complexes,or partial tendencies, which exist in his own mind—and in theaction of the novel he reads the conflicts and struggles which heexperiences in his own life. Precisely the same remarks areapplicable to the first-rate play. The reason that such produc-tions only appeal to a limited class is that they presuppose intheir audience the possession of mental processes sufficientlycomplicated to enable this identification to occur. It must beclearly understood, of course, that we are making no attemptto reduce all the psychological phenomena produced by thenovel and play to this single mechanism, but only to traceout one of the factors on which these works of art depend.

The mechanism of identification underlies many anomalous116

Page 130: The Psychology of Insanity

actions of whose real origin the individual himself is altogetherunconscious. One of my patients became involved withoutapparent reason in a lawsuit which an acquaintance wasbringing against his wife. He plunged into the case withextraordinary zeal, entirely neglected his own business, sup-plied his acquaintance with considerable funds, and did every-thing that was possible to further the latter's victory. WhenI inquired the reason of his behaviour, he assured me that hewas actuated solely by friendship and by a love of abstractjustice. In this, of course, the process which we have formerlydescribed as rationalisation will be easily recognised. Investi-gation showed that the alleged friendship was only of a fewweeks' standing, and that abstract justice was very obviouslyon the opposite side. The real cause of my patient's action wasfound by psychological analysis to be that he was himselfengaged in a bitter dispute with his own wife. He had thereforeunconsciously identified himself with the other man, whohappened to be in a similar situation. The same mechanismmay be observed in the example described on p. 61, of thepatient who was so disturbed at the ill-treatment inflictedupon two foreigners.

The stimulus which gives rise to the identification is often tobe found in the fact that the second individual possesses somecharacter or environment which is coveted by the first. This isseen in a simple form in the play of the child who 'pretends' tobe 'father', and thereby achieves the magical joys of beinggrown up. A more complicated variety of the same processplays a prominent part in the causation of many hystericalsymptoms. The numerous ills which occur in these cases arefrequently the result of unconscious identification with asecond individual who is afflicted with an organic disease,but who also has some other character which is strenuouslydesired by the patient. An hysterical patient of my own, forexample, suffered from severe attacks of vertigo—analysisshowed that his symptoms were entirely the result of identifica-tion with his father, who was the subject of chronic ear-disease,an affection often associated with vertigo.

117

Page 131: The Psychology of Insanity

Identification is intimately bound up with those day-dream-ing processes which have been dealt with in the earlier portionof the present chapter. The day-dreamer who witnesses thetriumphal progress of some popular hero through the streetslives himself into the part of the central figure, and marcheswith him through the cheering crowds. From this simple andwell-known phenomenon a chain of allied manifestations leadsfinally to the chronic wards of the hospital, where we encountera most distinguished assemblage of emperors, generals, andother representatives of the great.

118

Page 132: The Psychology of Insanity

CHAPTER XII

THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CONFLICT

I F we now review the field which we have surveyed in thepresent volume, and consider the implements which haveproved of value in the investigation of its details, we shall atonce observe that there are two of those implements whichhave been pressed into service at almost every turn. These arethe conceptions of dissociation and conflict, and their utilityhas been so great that it will be profitable to examine from amore comprehensive and general point of view the part whichthey play in mental life.

We have seen that a vast number of abnormal phenomena,ranging from hallucinations and delusions to the complicatedphantasy productions described in the last chapter, are to beregarded as examples of dissociation. The mind has lost thathomogeneity which is the ideal of the normal personality, andhas become disintegrated into more or less independent por-tions, each pursuing its own course and development withoutreference to the welfare of the whole.

We have seen, moreover, that this disintegration has invar-iably owed its existence to the presence of a conflict. Homo-geneity has disappeared because the mind contains elementswhich are incompatible with each other, and dissociation hasarisen as a method of avoiding the storm and stress which thewarring of these mutually hostile elements would otherwiseinevitably produce. Dissociation is therefore to be regardedbiologically as a refuge from the stress of conflict, and as one ofnature's methods of dealing with conflicts which seem insolubleby other means. Hence, if we would investigate the causesresponsible for abnormal mental phenomena, the discoverythat dissociation exists is only the first step in the process, andit is always necessary to pass further back to the conflict whichwill be found behind it.

Page 133: The Psychology of Insanity

Conflict, therefore, would seem to be a fundamental factorin the causation of mental disorder, and the determinationof its precise significance a problem of prime importance forpsychology and for science. At present the full significance ofconflict is imperfectly understood, and any general discussionof the subject must therefore be largely speculative in character.It will, nevertheless, be of interest to consider shortly thedeductions that may be drawn with some degree of confidencefrom the knowledge so far gained, and the directions in whichit would seem profitable to prosecute further research.

In the former chapters of this book our task has generallybeen the elucidation of some individual symptom, and wehave therefore not attempted to push the analysis of thepatient's mental condition further than was necessary for thispurpose. Hence in most cases the conflict which we have dis-covered to be immediately responsible for the genesis of thesymptom has been of a comparatively minor character, and thecomplexes concerned have involved only the more superficialelements of the mind.

When, however, a more profound analysis has been made,and the investigation has been carried sufficiently far to explainthe origin of the whole mental state, a conflict of a morefundamental character has finally been unearthed. Thisfundamental conflict involves factors of an importance com-mensurate with the effects produced, and generally leads usback to the great primary instincts which constitute the princi-pal driving forces of the mind. We find a struggle taking placein which one of these primary instincts is pitted against another,or in which the desires and tendencies arising from such aninstinct are opposed and thwarted by conditions enforced uponthe patient by his environment and circumstances. It maytherefore be concluded that in conflicts of these two types areprobably to be found the essential causes responsible for manyof the manifestations of mental disorder.

Freud considered that the origin of all cases belonging tocertain varieties of mental disease can be traced back tofactors connected with a single one of the great instincts, that

120

Page 134: The Psychology of Insanity

of sex. We should expect, of course, that the immense power ofthe sex impulses, and the opposition which inevitably arisesbetween them and the rules of conduct imposed by civilisedsociety, would make this instinct one of the most prevalentsources of conflict and mental disintegration. Nevertheless,Freud's generalisation has not been universally accepted and,even allowing for the fact that Freud's conception of sex is farwider than is covered by the ordinary use of the term, it isperhaps safer at the present time to assume that the conflictsin question may involve factors connected with any of thefundamental instinctive forces of the mind, provided that thesefactors are of sufficient emotional intensity. We shall readilyadmit that sex probably plays a predominant part in a major-ity of cases, but shall be prepared to find that a certain numberare dependent upon conflicts in which other mental elementsare mainly concerned.

Among the great primary instincts which provide the oppos-ing forces responsible for mental conflict a dominant placemust be assigned to 'herd instinct5.1 It has been explainedin chapter x (p. ioo) that a vast part of the beliefs and con-duct of man is due to the operation of this instinct. From itthe tendencies generally ascribed to tradition and to educationderive most of their power. It provides the mechanism bywhich the ethical code belonging to a particular class isenforced upon each individual member of that class, so that thelatter is instinctively impelled to think and to act in the mannerwhich the code prescribes. That is to say, a line of conductupon which the herd has set its sanction acquires all thecharacters of an instinctive action, although this line of con-duct may have no rational basis, may run counter to thedictates of experience, and may be in direct opposition to thetendencies generated by the other primary instincts. Thisopposition to other primary instincts is well exemplified in thecase of sex, where the impulses due to the latter are constantlybaulked and controlled by the opposing tendencies arisingfrom our moral education and tradition.

1 Cf. footnote on p. ioo.

121

Page 135: The Psychology of Insanity

It will be immediately obvious that in these strugglesbetween the primary instincts and the beliefs and codes en-forced by the operation of herd instinct we have a fertile fieldfor the development of mental conflict. Each of the factorsinvolved possesses an enormous emotional force, and weshould therefore expect that their opposition would producea plentiful crop of the abnormal mental phenomena describedin the preceding chapters of this book. Trotter, who has fullydeveloped the subject in the papers to which we have alreadyfrequently referred, has pointed out the immense significancewhich the conflict between primitive instinct and herd tradi-tion possesses for the human mind. He remarks that the mani-festations of mental disintegration thereby produced

are coming to be recognised over a larger and larger field,and in a great variety of phenomena. . . . This field includes apart of insanity, how much we cannot even guess, but certainlya very large part; it includes the group of conditions describedas functional diseases of the nervous system, and, finally, itincludes that vast group of the mentally unstable which, whiledifficult to define without detailed consideration, is sufficientlyprecise in the knowledge of all to be recognisable as extremelylarge.

In the last chapter we have described several cases in whichthe outbreak of insanity depended upon the existence of aconflict between the dominating complexes of the mind andthe circumstances in which the individual was compelled tolive. It was shown that the abnormal phenomena finallyproduced could be regarded as biological reactions whosepurpose was to provide a way of escape from the strain of thisintolerable struggle. The individual found a refuge in dissocia-tion, and retired into an imaginary world where the com-plexes attained a delusional fulfilment, while all the mentalprocesses incompatible with this imaginary world were shutout of the field of consciousness. Now in cases of this type it isinteresting to note that among the processes thus excludedfrom effectual participation in consciousness are to be foundalmost all the tendencies due to the operation of herd instinct.

122

Page 136: The Psychology of Insanity

The patients have lost the gregarious attributes of the normalman, and the sanctions of traditional conduct have no longerany significance for them. In the milder cases this change showsitself merely as a loss of interest in the affairs of their fellows,a tendency to be solitary and unsociable, an atrophy of theiraffections for friends and relatives, and an indifference to theordinary conventions of society. In the advanced cases thechange is much more marked, and the mind is completelywithdrawn from participation in the life of the herd. The codeof conduct imposed by convention and traditions no longerregulates the patient's behaviour, and he becomes slovenly,filthy, degraded, and shameless. In this picture, to which somany chronic patients conform, may be recognised theabsolute negation of herd instinct and of the vast group ofmental activities which arise therefrom.

These facts suggest the hypothesis that the fundamentalmechanism which underlies this vast group of the insanitiesconsists essentially in a dissociation of herd instinct. It ispossible that the individual who is faced with an intolerableconflict between his primitive instincts on the one hand, andhis environment and traditions on the other, and who hasfound a refuge by retiring into a world of phantasy and shut-ting out the world of reality, can only achieve this by disso-ciating herd instinct from the other primary forces of the mindand refusing to allow it any longer to play a part therein. Ifthis hypothesis should prove to be correct, prevention wouldresolve itself into the problem of how to obviate the underlyingdissociation. In order to achieve this it would be necessaryto deal with the conflict which had produced it, and the remedywould lie in attacking one or other of the antagonists so thatincompatibility no longer existed. The primitive instinctscannot presumably be altered, and the attack would thereforehave to be directed either against the traditions and codeswhich obtain their force from the operation of herd instinct or,naturally more hopefully, against the particular ways in whichthose traditions and codes are acting upon the mind of thepatient. It may be possible to modify these so that the flagrant

123

Page 137: The Psychology of Insanity

incompatibilities which produce these disastrous consequencesare no longer produced.

How far measures of this kind can be applied to those grossdisturbances which we have latterly been considering is highlyspeculative, but there can be no doubt that minor mentaldisorders, which are dependent upon conflicts of an essentiallysimilar character, though much less in degree, can be profitablyattacked along this road. Modern psychotherapy, which hasadvanced greatly since this book was first written, has shownhow much can be achieved in this way.

124

Page 138: The Psychology of Insanity

INDEXAction, stereotyped, 37, 38Activities, simultaneous, 41Adler, A., viii, 12Ajax, 15Alcoholism, 84, 92Alterations in speech, 37Amnesia, 33Anaesthesia, hysterical, 4, 17Apathy, 30, 32Argument, imperviousness to, 97,

Association experiment, 59, 60Astronomy, development of, 22Atomic theory, 23Auditory hallucinations, 34Automatic writing, 42, 43

Beliefs, non-rational, 98 ff.Betrothal-delirium, 109Bias, party, 56Bourne, Rev. Ansel, 46Brahe, Tycho, 22Breur, Josef, 3

Censure, 78, 81 ff.Cerebral topography, 19Charcot, 1Complex; Complexes, 26, 54 ff.

bias, 55normal action of, 54 ff.political, 56, 57, 60, 98repressed, action of, 78 ff.

Conceptions of mental disorder, 15demonological, 16, 18physiological, 4, 18, 19, 24, 26political, 18psychological, 15, 20, 21 ff., 28

Concepts, 24Conflict, 65 ff., 119 ff.Conolly, 19Conscious processes, 4, 25

Consciousness, 2dissociation of, 39 ff.field of, 40

Copernicus, 22Cynicism, 84

Dalton, 23Day-dreaming, 106 ff.Deficiency, mental, 29, 39Delusions, 34 ff, 97, 105

fixity of, 35of grandeur, 34, 71, n oof persecution, 34, 35, 92of reference, 35, 94secondary, 71

Dementia, 30, 39emotional, 32, 40, 104, 108senile, 30

Depression, 30, 31, 40Determinism, psychological, 53Development of psychopathology,

1 ff.Devil's claw, 17Devine, 82Dissociation, 2, 10, 39 ff., 105, 119

of consciousness, 41 ff.the result of conflict, 68, 69

Double personality, 45, 46, 69, 76Dreams, 5, 6, 7Drunkard's humour, 83

Ego, 7> 47and libido, 7, 12

Emotional dementia, 32, 40, 104,108

Esquirol, 19Excitement, 30, 40

manic, 31

Field of consciousness, 40Fixation of libido, 7Foreconscious, 5, 6

125

Page 139: The Psychology of Insanity

Forgetting, 73Freud, vi, viii. 3 ff., 20, 36, 53, 120

development of, 3 ff.sex theory of, 6, 7

Functional nervous disorders, 1

Grandiose delusions, 34, 71, n o

Hallucinations, 34, 69auditory, 34, 49tactile, 34visual, 34

Hanwell, 19Heinroth, 20Herd instinct, 100 ff., 121 ff.Hippocrates, 16, 18Hobbies, 54Homer, mental disorders in, 15Humanitarianism, development of,

18, 19Humour, 83Hypnotism, 8Hysteria, 1, 4, 5, 8, 42Hysterical anaesthesia, 4, 17

Identification, 115 ff.Insane, anti-social attribute of the,

104irrationality of the, 96 ff.

Insanitydemonological conception of, 16,

18Hippocratic conception of, 16, 18old maids', 93physiological conception of, 18, 20projection in, 92psychological conception of, 15,

20, 21 ff.Instinct, herd, 100 ff., 121 ff.Instincts, primary, 99, 100Irene, case of, 33, 44, 45, 47, 74, 75,

79Irrationality of the insane, 96 ff.Irritability, 62

James, William, 46, 99, 157Janet, P., vi, 2, 20, 33

Jekyll and Hyde, 46Jung, C. G., vi, viii, 8, 12, 20, 53,

54> 59> 60, 61, 79, 88, i n , 115

Kepler, 22, 23Kraepelin, 20Krafft-Ebing, vi

Libido, 6, 7development of, 7 ff.phases of, 7

Logic-tight compartment, 50, 67,68, 69, 72, 73, 74

Magnetism, 1Mania, washing, 36, 49, 84Manic excitement, 31McDougal, 54Mechanisms, 5, 11Medium, 15Mental capacity, defects of, 29

qualitative changes in, 30, 39Mental deficiency, 29, 39Mental disorders, history of, 15 ff.

phenomena of, 28 ff.Mental processes, unconscious, 26Mesmer, 1Mind, regions of, 5Motor-area, 20Mutism, 86

Nebuchadnezzar, 15Nervous disorders, functional, 1Neurasthenia, 1Neurotic cases, 33Non-rational beliefs, 101, 102

Obsession, 36, 48, 69Old maid's insanity, 93Old Testament, mental disorders in,

15

Party bias, 56, 98Pearson, Karl, vi, 22Persecution, delusions of, 34 ff., 71,

92, 93, 104

126

Page 140: The Psychology of Insanity

Personality, 47, 65double, 45, 46, 69, 76

Perversion, sexual, 7Phantasy, 106 ff.Phraseology, alterations in, 37Pinel, 19Prejudice, 91Projection, 89, 90 ff.Prudery, 81, 82, 93Psychiatry, 19Psychoanalysis, 8

orthodox school of, 11, 37, 100Psychological determinism, 53Psychopathology, development of,

1 ff., 10 ff.

Rationalisation, 57, 58, 70, 97Reaction time, 59Reaction word, 59Reference, delusions of, 35, 94Repressed complexes, action of,

78 ff.Repression, 4, 6, 26, 72 ff.Resistance, 4

Sanity v. insanity, 103, 104, 105Saul, 15Science, method of, 21 ff.Self-deception, 57

Self-reproach, 91, 94Sentiment, 54Sex, evolution of, 6, 7Shand, 54Shyness, 82Somnambulism, 33, 44, 45, 46, 47,

69, 74 ff., 7^Speech, alterations in, 37Spes phthisica, 83Spiritualism, 43Stereotyped action, 37, 88Suggestion, 1, 2Symbolisation, 88Sympathy, 115

Test, association, 59, 60Topography, cerebral, 19Trotter, W., vi, 85, 99, 100, 101, 122

Ulysses, 15Unconscious mental processes, 4, 26Unconscious region of mind, 4, 5, 6

Vorbeireden, 85

Washing mania, 36, 49, 84Wish-fulfilment, 109Witchcraft, 17Writing, automatic, 42, 43

127